The Christian God and the Problem of Evil

Both Mung and KeithS have asked me to weigh in on the question of whether the existence of evil counts as a good argument against Christianity, as KeithS has maintained in a recent post, so I shall oblige.

It is important to understand that the problem of evil is not an argument against the existence of God or gods, but against what KeithS calls the Christian God (actually, the God of classical theism), Who is supposed to be omniscient, omnipotent and omnibenevolent. KeithS succinctly formulates the problem as follows:

Let’s say I claim that an omniGod named Frank exists — omniscient, omnipotent, and omnibenevolent. Suppose I also claim that Frank regards seahorses as the absolute height of evil. The world contains a lot of seahorses, and Frank, being omnipotent, has the power to wipe them off the face of the earth. Why doesn’t he? Why does he countenance a world full of seahorses?

KeithS emphasizes that it is not enough for the Christian to show that God is on balance benevolent. Rather, the Christian needs to defend the claim that God is omnibenevolent:

The Christian claim is that God is omnibenevolent — as benevolent as it is logically possible to be. Finding that the items on the “good” side of the ledger outweigh those on the “bad” side — if that were the case — would not establish God’s omnibenevolence at all.

Finally, KeithS provides his own take on the problem of evil:

The problem of evil remains as much of a problem as ever for Christians. Yet there are obvious solutions to the problem that fit the evidence and are perfectly reasonable: a) accept that God doesn’t exist, or b) accept that God isn’t omnipotent, or c) accept that God isn’t perfectly benevolent. Despite the availability of these obvious solutions, most Christians will choose to cling to a view of God that has long since been falsified.

He even suggests how he would resolve the problem if he were a theist (emphasis mine – VJT):

Suppose God hates evil and suffering but is too weak to defeat them, at least at the moment. Then any such instances can be explained by God’s weakness.

It addresses the problem of evil without sacrificing theism. I’m amazed that more theists don’t seize on this sort of resolution. They’re too greedy in their theology, too reluctant to give up the omnis.

I think KeithS is onto something here. In fact, I’d like to ditch the conventional Christian views of God’s omniscience, omnipotence and omnibenevolence. It’s time for an overhaul.

Why a God Who constantly watches His creatures cannot be omniscient

First, the conventional notion of God’s omniscience needs to be jettisoned. As I argued in an earlier post on the problem of evil, the problem of evil depends on the assumption that God’s knowledge of our choices (and of Adam and Eve’s choices) is logically prior to those choices. In that post, I upheld the contrary view (defended in our own time by C.S. Lewis), that God is like a watcher on a high hill: He timelessly knows everything that we choose to do, but His knowledge is logically subsequent to the choices we make, which means that He doesn’t know what we will do “before” He decides to make us. I have to acknowledge, however, that this is very much a minority view among the Christian Fathers and/or Doctors of the Church, and I can only think of two who argued for this view: namely, the somewhat heterodox theologian Origen (185-254 A.D.) and possibly, the Christian philosopher Boethius (c. 480- c. 524 A.D. – although his own personal views on the subject remain in dispute, as he elsewhere seems to reject the “watcher on the hill” analogy which he develops in Book V, Prose 6 of his Consolation of Philosophy, in which he declares that God “sees all things in an eternal present just as humans see things in a non-eternal present.”) Whether they be predestinationists or Molinists, the vast majority of Christian theologians who are orthodox – and I’m not counting “open theists” here – maintain that God’s knowledge of our choices is logically prior to those choices. I haven’t taken a straw poll of lay Christian believers, but judging from Christians I’m acquainted with, the “watcher on the hill” view of God remains a popular way of reconciling His foreknowledge with human free will, to this day. I believe the common folk are wiser than the theologians here.

Why are theologians so reluctant to accept the Boethian solution? In a nutshell, because they see it as detracting from God’s sovereignty, as it makes Him dependent on His creatures for information about what is going on in the world. God has to (timelessly) observe us in order to know what we are getting up to. I have to say I don’t see the problem here, provided that God freely and timelessly chooses to rely on His creatures for His knowledge of what they do. If He wants to impose that limitation on Himself, who are we to stop Him?

But if God’s knowledge of our choices is (timelessly) obtained from observing those choices, then we can no longer say that God knows exactly what I would do in every possible situation. On the Boethian account, God does not possess counterfactual knowledge: He knows everything I do, but not everything I would do, in all possible situations. Why not? For one thing, in many situations, there simply is no fact of the matter as to what I would do. What would I do if I won $10,000,000? I don’t know, and neither does God. Nor is this a bad thing: after all, if God knows exactly what I would do in every possible situation, then it makes no sense to say that in a given situation, I could have acted otherwise. (That, by the way, is why I find Molinism utterly nonsensical.)

And what about mathematics? Does God know the answer to every possible mathematical problem? I would argue that He doesn’t, as there are many branches of mathematics where the “rules of the game” are determined by the mathematicians theorizing in that area. In a different world, we would have had different mathematicians, and different branches of mathematics, with different rules. I see no reason to suppose that God knows all possible choices that could be made by all possible (as well as actual) persons.

The upshot of all this is that while God knows everything there is to know about His creatures, He is not omniscient. There are many counterfactuals that He doesn’t know, and there are many possibilities that He never contemplates, either. All we can say is that God knows everything about what we do (past, present and future), and that we can keep no secrets from Him.

Why God is a lot less powerful than many Christians think

Second, the traditional notion of God’s omnipotence needs to be discarded. On the classical view defended by St. Thomas Aquinas, God can do anything which it is logically possible for Him to do, as God. In recent years, however, the classical view has come under fire, from the Reformed theologian Alvin Plantinga, who refuted it using the humorous counter-example of a being whose nature allows him to do nothing but scratch his ear (which he does, making him omnipotent) in his book, God and other minds (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1967), and also from the Catholic philosopher Peter Geach, who sharply criticized the traditional view in an influential article titled “Omnipotence” (Philosophy 48 (1973): 7-20 – see here for a discussion). In his article, Geach argued that God is not omnipotent but almighty: since He maintains the world in existence, He has power over all things, but He does not have the power to do all things.

What relevance does this have to the problem of evil? On the traditional view of God’s omnipotence, God could have preserved each of us from sin throughout our earthly lives, without violating our free will, as he did with Jesus and (according to Catholics and Orthodox) the Virgin Mary: we would still have possessed full libertarian freedom when choosing between alternative goods, but not when choosing between good and evil. And there are many Protestants who believe that individuals who are “born again” are infallibly elected by God, so that even if they sin, their final salvation is Divinely guaranteed. Why, one might ask, didn’t God make us all like that? The Catechism of the Catholic Church attempts to resolve the problem by appealing to the “greater good” of the Incarnation and Redemption – a response which I find unsatisfactory, since (as Blessed John Duns Scotus argued) there was nothing to stop God from becoming incarnate even if Adam had never sinned.

For normal human beings, their personal identity is determined by their parentage, and by the gametes from which their bodies were created. (I would not be “me” if I had had a different mother or father, or if I had been conceived from a different sperm or egg.) But what if God’s act of specially electing a saint to glory also determines that individual’s personal identity? In that case, there is no way that God could have refrained from electing that saint without making him or her a different person. And if I am not elected in this fashion, but possess the power to choose between being saved and being damned, then I cannot coherently wish to have been predestined for eternal life without wishing myself to be a different person. It follows from this that while God could have made a world of human beings who were all preserved from sin, or who were all infallibly elected, not even God could make a world in which each of us is preserved from sin or infallibly elected. In that case, God is significantly less powerful than Christian theologians like to imagine.

In recent years, New Atheists have argued that the designs we find in living things are inept, and that if a Creator existed, He could have done a much better job of making these creatures. Creationists and Intelligent Design advocates reply that living things are subject to numerous design constraints, and that just because we can imagine a more elegant design does not mean that it is possible to create such a design. Picturability does not imply possibility. Recent scientific discoveries regarding the vertebrate eye (see here and here) have done much to vindicate this line of argument. (The same goes for the laryngeal nerve in the neck of the giraffe.) We are a long way here from the traditional view that God can make anything, as long as no logical contradiction is involved. Physical and nomological constraints (relating to the structure of matter, and the laws of Nature which obtain in our cosmos) also need to be taken into account.

An additional reason for rejecting the traditional notion of omnipotence is that it commits one to maintaining that God can bring about states of affairs which are not properly described. When someone claims, for instance, that God could make a horse capable of flying, like the mythical Pegasus, what, exactly, are we supposed to conceive of God doing here? And how would Pegasus fly, anyway? Are we supposed to imagine God working a miracle, by raising a horse in the air? But in that case, shouldn’t we really say that the horse is not flying (by its own natural power), but rather that God is holding it up? Or are we meant to imagine an alternative world, where the laws of Nature are changed so as to allow horses to fly – in which case, should we call the creature in this alternate world a horse, or should we rather call it a shmorse? Or are we to suppose that God could come up with a physical design for a horse that would enable it to fly, even with the laws of Nature that hold in this world? But in that case, how do we know that such a design exists? There is not the slightest evidence for such a design, and aerodynamic considerations suggest that the enterprise of attaching natural wings that would allow an animal with the dimensions of a horse to fly, would be altogether unworkable.

Goodbye to omnibenevolence

Finally, the concept of God’s omnibenevolence needs to be tossed out, lock, stock and barrel. Theologians have always maintained, of course, that God could have made a world that was better than the one He did, simply by adding a few extra bells and whistles. There is no “best possible world,” as the philosopher Leibniz falsely imagined. But that does not prevent God from making a world which is free from all natural and moral evil – which raises the obvious question of why an omnibenevolent Deity would create such a world as ours. One traditional answer, given by St. Augustine in his Enchiridion, Chapter III, is that God allows evil for the sake of a “greater good”: “For the Omnipotent God, whom even the heathen acknowledge as the Supreme Power over all, would not allow any evil in his works, unless in his omnipotence and goodness, as the Supreme Good, he is able to bring forth good out of evil.” I think its time to candidly acknowledge, as Orthodox theologian David Bentley Hart has already done, that this kind of talk simply won’t wash:

Being infinitely sufficient in Himself, God had no need of a passage through sin and death to manifest His glory in His creatures or to join them perfectly to Himself. This is why it is misleading (however soothing it may be) to say that the drama of fall and redemption will make the final state of things more glorious than it might otherwise have been. No less metaphysically incoherent – though immeasurably more vile – is the suggestion that God requires suffering and death to reveal certain of his attributes (capricious cruelty, perhaps? morbid indifference? a twisted sense of humor?). It is precisely sin, suffering, and death that blind us to God’s true nature…

I do not believe we Christians are obliged – or even allowed – to look upon the devastation visited upon the coasts of the Indian Ocean and to console ourselves with vacuous cant about the mysterious course taken by God’s goodness in this world, or to assure others that some ultimate meaning or purpose resides in so much misery.

But as KeithS has pointed out, there are problems with Hart’s own resolution of the problem of evil:

So in Hart’s bizarre world, we have a God who supposedly hates evil and suffering, yet chooses to permit them — and somehow this is all okay because it’s only temporary. Good will triumph in the end.

KeithS suggested that the problem of evil would be soluble if Christians simply acknowledged that God isn’t omnipotent or perfectly benevolent, but noted that Christians continue to “cling to a view of God that has long since been falsified.”

So I’d like to make a proposal of my own. In the first place, I’d like to propose that God is benevolent only in relation to the persons whom He decides to create. “Prior to” His act of creation, God is not benevolent at all. Thus when deciding what kind of world to create, God makes no attempt to choose the best one, or even a perfect one (i.e. one free from evil). Only after having chosen a particular world (for reasons best known to Himself) can we speak of God as being benevolent to His creatures.

In the second place, I’d like to propose that God’s benevolence to His sentient and sapient creatures is not unrestricted. After all, He allows His own creatures to be tortured to death, on occasion. Nevertheless, God is perfectly capable of setting limits to the amount of pain we have to put up with (thankfully, none of us has to suffer one million years of torture), of healing whatever wounds (physical and psychic) His tortured creatures have endured, and of bestowing the gift of immortality upon His sentient and sapient creatures (provided that they do not spurn it). Thus according to the picture I am sketching, God is ultimately benevolent, but not omnibenevolent. On this side of eternity, God’s benevolence is quite modest – but we can at least console ourselves with the thought that life could be much, much more painful than it is.

Finally, I’d like to point out that Christians have never referred to God in their prayers as omnibenevolent, but rather as all-loving. God loves each and every one of us with a steadfast, unshakable love which is greater than any of us can possibly imagine. The only kind of love we can compare to God’s love, in its steadfastness, is parental love. And most importantly, what God loves is we ourselves, and not our feelings. Thus God has no interest in maximizing the level of euphoria in the world – whether it be the aggregate level or the average level – because God’s parental commitment is to us, and not our states of mind. Being a loving Father, God naturally wants what is ultimately best for us, but He does not necessarily want us to enjoy a pain-free journey to our ultimate destination.

These proposals of mine have significant implications for the problem of evil. On the Judeo-Christian view, each and every human person is a being of infinite and irreplaceable value, loved by God. Two infinities cannot be meaningfully added to yield a greater infinity; hence a world with more people would not be a “better” world. What’s more, even wicked people are beings of infinite and irreplaceable value; hence a world with kinder people would not be a “better” world, but merely a world where people existed in a better state. Thus I would suggest that one reason why God tolerates evil acts (such as acts of rape or murder) is that there are some individuals in our world who would never have come into existence, were it not for these evil acts having been performed. The same logic can be applied to natural disasters: think of a man and a woman, living in neighboring towns, who both lose their families in a terrible earthquake, but are brought together in the aftermath of the quake, and who decide to get married, settle down and raise a family of their own. Such occurrences are by no means uncommon. Since the creation of any human being is good in an unqualified sense, God may decide to tolerate natural or moral evils, if doing so enables individuals to come into existence who would not have done so otherwise. Please note that I’m not saying He must, but merely that He may.

Fair enough; nevertheless, the skeptic might urge, the world is still a pretty awful place, and arguably much worse than it needs to be. Most natural and moral evils don’t result in the creation of new sentient or sapient beings, after all. There seems to be a lot of gratuitous evil in the world. Why is this so?

The Fall – and why it is needed to explain the mess we’re in

Traditionally, Christians have appealed to the doctrine of the Fall of our first parents at the dawn of human history, in order to explain why God allows these senseless evils to continue. John Henry Newman eloquently argued for this doctrine in his Apologia pro Vita Sua (Longmans, Green & Co., London, revised edition, 1865, chapter 5, pp. 242-243):

I can only answer, that either there is no Creator, or this living society of men is in a true sense discarded from His presence. Did I see a boy of good make and mind, with the tokens on him of a refined nature, cast upon the world without provision, unable to say whence he came, his birthplace or his family connexions, I should conclude that there was some mystery connected with his history, and that he was one, of whom, from one cause or other, his parents were ashamed. Thus only should I be able to account for the contrast between the promise and the condition of his being. And so I argue about the world;— if there be a God, since there is a God, the human race is implicated in some terrible aboriginal calamity. It is out of joint with the purposes of its Creator. This is a fact, a fact as true as the fact of its existence; and thus the doctrine of what is theologically called original sin becomes to me almost as certain as that the world exists, and as the existence of God.

In their recent book, Adam and the Genome, geneticist Dennis Venema and New Testament scholar Scott McKnight have marshaled an impressive array of converging scientific evidence, indicating that the human population has probably never fallen below 10,000 individuals. That certain puts paid to literalistic interpretations of the Fall, but as Denis Alexander has described in his book, Creation or Evolution: Do We Have to Choose?, one can still defend some notion of a Fall at the dawn of human history. Here’s how he outlines one possible approach to the Fall (although it’s not his favorite):

In the first type of approach (which has many variants), some people in Africa, following the emergence of anatomically modern humanity, became aware of God’s existence, power and calling upon their lives and responded to their new-found knowledge of him in love and obedience, in authentic relationship with God. However, they subsequently turned their back on the light that they had received and went their own way, leading to human autonomy and a broken relationship with God (“sin”). The emphasis in this type of speculation is on historical process – relationships built and broken over many generations.

My own belief is that God bestowed upon our first parents the responsibility for deciding the scope of Divine providence in ordinary human affairs. In their pride, our first parents chose personal autonomy, knowing that it would entail death and suffering for the entire human race: basically, they told God to butt out of everyday human affairs, leaving Him free to intervene only for very special reasons. To skeptics who would object that God should never have given such enormous responsibilities to our first parents in the first place, I would suggest that it is simply impossible for God to make intelligent beings without offering them an allotted sphere or domain in which they can legitimately exercise their freedom: that is what makes them who they are. As the first parents of the human race, our first parents had to have the responsibility for deciding whether they wanted the human race to be protected by God’s Providence or whether to reject God and go it alone.

As a Christian, I believe that God is just and merciful. I do not believe that it was unjust of God to test the human race at the beginning of human history; but I will acknowledge that in order to make sense of the terrible consequences of that fateful test, we need to maintain a view of history which sounds very strange to modern ears – instead of a gradual ascent to human self-awareness, as we might suppose, there was a First Contact between human creatures and their Creator. We need to envisage this as a cosmic, Miltonian drama, with our first parents as larger-than-life characters who enjoyed an intimacy and familiarity with God which we can only dream of, and who were given the enormous responsibility of custodianship over the lives of their future descendants. It may seem incomprehensible to us that they would give up their relationship with a God Who could satisfy all their needs, in favor of a death-and-violence ridden world like ours, but what they gained (in their own eyes) was the freedom to live as they chose. This, then, is why we’re in the mess we’re in. How long it will continue, I have no idea.

For those readers who would like a theological explanation of animal suffering, I would recommend Jon Garvey’s excellent online book, God’s Good Earth.

The problem of evil: A summary

We have seen that in order to make sense of the evil in the world, we need to abandon the notion of an omniscient God Who knows all counterfactuals and all possibilities, and Who knows what we do without needing to be informed by us. Rather, we should simply say that God (timelessly) knows everything we do, by constantly watching us. We also need to abandon the notion of an omnipotent God Who can do anything that’s logically possible. It turns out that there are a number of constraints which God is subject to, which prevent Him from creating any old world that we can imagine, and that prevent Him from having created us in a perfect world where no-one ever sinned. Furthermore, we need to abandon the notion that God is omnibenevolent. Christians have never worshiped an omnibenevolent Deity. Rather, the God they worship is a Parent Who loves us personally, and Who will never stop loving us. Such a God may however be willing to allow His creatures to be subjected to a great degree of suffering in the short term. He can only be called “benevolent” from a long-term perspective, insofar as He has prepared us for eternity with Him.

Finally, the sheer pervasiveness of the suffering in this world points to what Newman referred to as “some terrible aboriginal calamity” at the dawn of humanity, in which the entire human race paid the price for the proud decision made by our first parents to isolate themselves from God’s benevolent protection, for the sake of pursuing what they perceived as independence and freedom. God did not know that they would make that choice, but He gave them the power to decide the fate of the human race, and to “turn off the lights” in our world until God started turning them back on again, culminating in His Revelation of Himself to us 2,000 years ago in a manger in Bethlehem.

To sum up: the Christian view of history is capable of being cogently defended, provided Christians are willing to remove the theological barnacles that have attached themselves to its system of belief, and abandon the “three omnis,” in favor of a more intimate but less extravagant notion of God.

1,030 thoughts on “The Christian God and the Problem of Evil

  1. fifthmonarchyman: here is a very old article with another alternative theodicy

    http://www.leaderu.com/theology/theodicy.html

    Just finished reading that big pile of… theodicy.

    So to sum it up, whatever God decrees is good by definition. The perceived evil is no such thing just because calvinists say so. “Evil exists for good reasons”

    How cute. Is evil which exists for good reasons evil at all?

    So I guess that according to FMM, if I don’t keep the kid from falling off that cliff, I’m
    being evil. OTOH, If God does the same thing, that’s all fine and dandy.

    What does that mean for moral objectivity?

    ETA: Calvinism, or the doctrine of “do as I say, not as I do”

  2. Acartia:
    Personally I don’t think that there is any objective evil. Something’s “virtue”, or value comes from individual perspective. Although the vast majority of us would refer to the holocaust as evil. But there were, and still are, some people who perceive it as a good. We would consider these people to be pathological in some respect, but you can’t argue that they don’t feel that it was a good thing.

    Good and bad can only be categorized when compared. For example. I think that we would all agree that giving a starving child some bread is a good thing. But what if we had armloads of nutritious food and still only have that starving child some bread? Good? Bad?

    I haven’t seen a solid argument for objective good, but I find Granny Weatherwax’s views on sin compelling:

    “…And that’s what your holy men discuss, is it?” [asked Granny Weatherwax.]
    “Not usually. There is a very interesting debate raging at the moment on the nature of sin. for example.” [answered Mightily Oats.]
    “And what do they think? Against it, are they?”
    “It’s not as simple as that. It’s not a black and white issue. There are so many shades of gray.”
    “Nope.”
    “Pardon?”
    “There’s no grays, only white that’s got grubby. I’m surprised you don’t know that. And sin, young man, is when you treat people like things. Including yourself. That’s what sin is.”
    “It’s a lot more complicated than that–”
    “No. It ain’t. When people say things are a lot more complicated than that, they means they’re getting worried that they won’t like the truth. People as things, that’s where it starts.”
    “Oh, I’m sure there are worse crimes–”
    “But they starts with thinking about people as things…”
    –from Carpe Jugulum, by Terry Pratchett.

    (Apologies if I’ve posted this before.)

  3. Patrick,

    I would be very interested in seeing the historical evidence you claim exists. To the best of my knowledge there isn’t any.

    The writings of John, Mark, Luke and Mathew.

  4. dazz,

    The answer seems simple doesn’t it? Well you are right, it is simple! While it is true that their names have not “been signed on the dotted line” of any of the copies of the gospels that have been found, scholars and the early church both affixed the names of the authors with their gospels.

    Matthew, a tax collector also known as Levi and one of the twelve disciples, wrote the first gospel in the New Testament of Matthew. John Mark, who was a friend of the disciple Peter, wrote the Book of Mark. And Luke, who was Paul’s doctor, wrote the book of Luke and the Acts of the Apostles.

    Do you agree with this?

  5. colewd:
    dazz,

    Do you agree with this?

    Not an expert by any means, but all I’ve read suggests that most scholars believe that none of them was written by any of the apostles. So no, I don’t agree if most scholars disagree

  6. dazz,

    Not an expert by any means, but all I’ve read suggests that most scholars believe that none of them was written by any of the apostles. So no, I don’t agree if most scholars disagree

    Thanks. I hope others will weigh in.

  7. colewd:

    I would be very interested in seeing the historical evidence you claim exists. To the best of my knowledge there isn’t any.

    The writings of John, Mark, Luke and Mathew.

    “Historical” seems to be another word you don’t understand. Here’s a timeline of when those books were written:

    There is no (none, nada, zilch) contemporaneous evidence for even the existence of Jesus let alone anything he might have done.

    It’s painfully clear that you were not convinced to be a Christian by actual evidence. Why say otherwise?

  8. walto: People who think that all such judgments are subjective have to be ok with the view that the Holocaust was a good thing is just as acceptable as the view that the Holocaust was a bad thing.

    Your beginning to sound like William J. Murray. That, in itself, should give you cause for thought.

    Why do I have to be OK with anyone else’s view? I think that the holocaust was “evil”. I certainly don’t have to believe that the view that it was good is as acceptable as my view.

  9. dazz: Not an expert by any means, but all I’ve read suggests that most scholars believe that none of them was written by any of the apostles. So no, I don’t agree if most scholars disagree

    From my readings and background, there’s little to no evidence that the gospels are written by their namesakes. Secondary evidence points to the fact that the attributions came long after the pieces were written for instance. I’ll note that my sister is a biblical scholar, so I’ve had a lot of exposure to the basis of analysis, for what it’s worth.

    That said, my issue with people claiming that the bible and particularly the gospels are historical evidence has nothing to do with the anonymity of the authors. All sorts of anonymous records are considered historical, so that’s not actually a big issue.

    The issue from my perspective is simply technical: the scholarly world considers the bible and the stories therein to be historical source(s). Historians and scholars use such sources in conjunction with all sorts of other material to reconstruct an historical picture. As the picture of events comes together, the underlying material supporting specific contextual understanding is then classified as historical evidence.

    The point is, simply saying that the “Matthew”, “Mark”, “Luke”, or “John” stories are “historical evidence” is a nonsensical statement. For something to be historical evidence, it has to be considered relevant to a specific historical question by someone who actually has some expertise with the relevant historical context.

  10. If I think all views are subjective, then I certainly don’t have to give any weight to other people’s views.

    Perhaps my subjective view is that subjective views are a little bit like votes, and the view with the most adherents is the dominant view. It’s still my subjective view.

    Or my subjective view is that the golden rule is a good rule, in which case I might subjectively judge actions by how I would feel as the object of the action.

  11. colewd: Thanks. I hope others will weigh in.

    There is extremely solid evidence that the Gospels were written by the folks they were attributed to.

    For starters despite three of the four authors being minor secondary figures in the early church and despite their being no internal claim of authorship there was never any dispute in the early church as to who that actual authors were.

    Considering the geological cultural and theological spread of the movement. It’s utterly amazing that no one claimed that anyone wrote these works other than the folks we attribute them to.

    also check this out

    10 Misconceptions about the NT Canon: #9: “The Canonical Gospels Were Certainly Not Written by the Individuals Named in Their Titles”

    peace

  12. colewd: Thanks. I hope others will weigh in.

    More importantly there is near universal acceptance that the Apostle Paul a companion and close associate of the original 12 disciples wrote most of the books attributed to him. Theses books are very early indeed beginning less than 25 years after resurrection.

    They have a very highly developed Christology and take for granted the important events in the life of Christ that are described in the Gospels.

    peace

  13. Patrick,

    There is no (none, nada, zilch) contemporaneous evidence for even the existence of Jesus let alone anything he might have done.

    Interesting. Can you support this claim?

    Others disagree:

    Scholars who specialize in the origins of Christianity agree on very little, but they do generally agree that it is most likely that a historical preacher, on whom the Christian figure “Jesus Christ” is based, did exist. The numbers of professional scholars, out of the many thousands in this and related fields, who don’t accept this consensus, can be counted on the fingers of one hand. Many may be more cautious about using the term “historical fact” about this idea, since as with many things in ancient history it is not quite as certain as that. But it is generally regarded as the best and most parsimonious explanation of the evidence and therefore the most likely conclusion that can be drawn.
    The opposite idea—that there was no historical Jesus at all and that “Jesus Christ” developed out of some purely mythic ideas about a non-historical, non-existent figure—has had a checkered history over the last 200 years, but has usually been a marginal idea at best. Its heyday was in the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, when it seemed to fit with some early anthropological ideas about religions evolving along parallel patterns and being based on shared archetypes, as characterized by Sir James Frazer’s influential comparative religion study The Golden Bough (1890). But it fell out of favor as the twentieth century progressed and was barely held by any scholars at all by the 1960s.

  14. dazz: Lulz

    The early church was extremely diverse group consisting of folks who often could not stand one other and differed on all most every thing except who wrote the Gospels.

    We are not talking about a bureaucracy or click here we are talking about folks that even considered each other to be heretics. But they agreed on this

    peace

  15. fifthmonarchyman: The early church was extremely diverse group consisting of folks who often could not stand one other and differed on all most every thing except who wrote the Gospels

    peace

    Imagine if we didn’t have all of the writings of every single Christian group from back then.

    Glen Davidson

  16. GlenDavidson: Imagine if we didn’t have all of the writings of every single Christian group from back then.

    We have lots of them and there is absolutely no reason to believe that the writings that don’t have would alter our conception much

    remember unlike Islam In Christianity there was no controlling authority that could suppress the writings of groups that they did not like.

    If a writing is lost it’s due to the fact that it was probably never very popular in the first place

    peace

  17. fifthmonarchyman: If a writing is lost it’s due to the fact that it was probably never very popular in the first place*

    Tell that to the Gnostics.

    My God, you certainly don’t know much.

    Glen Davidson

    *Thanks to the careful efforts of someone at Nag Hammedi to preserve Gnostic texts, yes, eventually we ended up with many of the Gnostic suppressed texts. But we used to have none except what the orthodox quoted, and we hardly have all of them now.

  18. GlenDavidson: Thanks to the careful efforts of someone at Nag Hammedi to preserve Gnostic texts, yes, eventually we ended up with many of the Gnostic suppressed texts.

    Exactly, we have the texts that they valued enough to preserve and nothing in them challenges our understanding of the authorship of the 4 Gospels

    Nothing prevented other unorthodox groups from doing the same thing. No one had the power to stop them.

    Many of these unorthodox groups were in places that were beyond even the reach of the Roman Empire.

    But they all agree on who wrote the 4 gospels

    peace

  19. keiths:
    CharlieM,

    That’s just the “God works in mysterious ways” defense.When something great happens, credit goes to God, no questions asked.When something horrible happens that God could have prevented, the rationalizations come pouring forth, including the classic “Who are we to judge? God works in mysterious ways.”

    One of my favorite strategies for evaluating defenses and theodicies is to ask how well the logic works for defending the opposite hypothesis: that God is perfectly evil.

    Let’s say you believe in a perfectly evil God, and someone is trying to convince you that your God doesn’t exist. They point to a wonderful event and say “a perfectly evil God wouldn’t allow something this good to happen.”You respond by saying “Who are you to judge?My perfectly evil God works in mysterious ways.That wonderful event was in the service of a higher evil that you and I can’t comprehend.”

    The same reasoning supports two diametrically opposed hypotheses. It’s a bad argument.

    Yes I agree, to say that God works in mysterious ways might be a personal belief but it is indeed a bad argument and one that I would not make.

    I was not making an argument for God, I was making the claim that neither you nor I have the knowledge required to judge the event.

    Steiner discusses how Jacob Boehme deals with God and evil below:

    Mysticism at the Dawn of the Modern Age

    “When I wrestled and fought, with God’s assistance, there arose a wondrous light in my soul which was altogether foreign to wild nature, and by which I first understood what God and man are, and what God has to do with man.” Jacob Boehme no longer feels himself to be a separate personality which utters its insights; he feels himself to be an organ of the great universal spirit which speaks in him. The limits of his personality do not appear to him as limits of the spirit which speaks out of him. For him this spirit is omnipresent. He knows that “the sophist will censure him” when he speaks of the beginning of the world and of its creation, “since I was not there and did not see it myself. Let him be told that in the essence of my soul and body, when I was not yet the I, but Adam’s essence, I was indeed there, and that I myself have forfeited my felicity in Adam.” It is only in external similes that Boehme can intimate how the light broke forth within himself…

    Boehme was not making speculations about the nature of God, he came to God through experience.

    Steiner continues:
    …For how can a conception explain the world which leaves the existing inharmonious elements aside, unexplained? Disharmony must be explained through harmony, evil through good itself. In speaking of these things, let us limit ourselves to good and evil; in the latter, disharmony in the narrower sense finds its expression in human life. For this is what Jacob Boehme basically limits himself to. He can do this, for to him nature and man appear as one essence. He sees similar laws and processes in both. The non-functional is for him an evil in nature, just as the evil is for him something non-functional in human destiny. Here and there it is the same basic forces which are at work. To one who has understood the origin of evil in man, the origin of evil in nature is also plain. — How is it possible for evil as well as for good to flow out of the same primordial essence? If one speaks in the spirit of Jacob Boehme, one gives the following answer: The primordial essence does not exist in itself alone. The diversity of the world participates in this existence. As the human body does not live its life as a single part, but as a multiplicity of parts, so too does the primordial essence. And as human life is poured into this multiplicity of parts, so is the primordial essence poured into the diversity of the things of this world. Just as it is true that the whole man has one life, so is it true that each part has its own life. And it no more contradicts the whole harmonious life of man that his hand should turn against his own body and wound it, than it is impossible that the things of the world, which live the life of the primordial essence in their own way, should turn against one another. Thus the primordial life, in distributing itself over different lives, bestows upon each life the capacity of turning itself against the whole. It is not out of the good that the evil flows, but out of the manner in which the good lives. As the light can only shine when it penetrates the darkness, so the good can only come to life when it permeates its opposite. Out of the “abyss” of darkness shines the light; out of the “abyss” of the indifferent, the good brings itself forth. And as in the shadow it is only brightness which requires a reference to light, while the darkness is felt to be self-evident, as something that weakens the light, so too in the world it is only the lawfulness in all things which is sought, and the evil, the non-functional, which is accepted as the self-evident. Hence, although for Jacob Boehme the primordial essence is the All, nothing in the world can be understood unless one keeps in sight both the primordial essence and its opposite. “The good has swallowed the evil or the repugnant into itself … Every being has good and evil within itself; and in its development, having to decide between them, it becomes an opposition of qualities, since one of them seeks to overcome the other.” It is therefore entirely in the spirit of Jacob Boehme to see both good and evil in every object and process of the world; but it is not in his spirit to seek the primordial essence without further ado in the mixture of the good with the evil. The primordial essence had to swallow the evil, but the evil is not a part of the primordial essence. Jacob Boehme seeks the primordial foundation of the world, but the world itself arose out of the abyss by means of the primordial foundation. “The external world is not God, and in eternity is not to be called God, but is only a being in which God reveals Himself … When one says, God is everything, God is heaven and earth and also the external world, then this is true; for everything has its origin from Him and in Him. But what am I to do with such a saying that is not a religion?”

    These are thought provoking views on God and evil.

    That which we do to each other we are doing to God. He who seeks and finds his brother and sister have sought and found God. We are in him all one body with many members, each of which has its own functions.

    Jacob Boehme, Threefold Life.

  20. dazz: Sure! it work both ways: whatever you do or don’t, evil or good, could be part of the Great plan. Why care about moral decisions then?

    um because they are moral.

    There is nothing inconsistent with me doing something immoral but God using it for Good. That does not mean my actions are not immoral it just means that there is more than one perspective at play

    quote:

    As for you, you meant evil against me, but God meant it for good, to bring it about that many people should be kept alive, as they are today.
    (Gen 50:20)

    end quote:

    Joseph’s brothers did an immoral thing but God used their actions to bring about the moral good of saving the lives of many people.

    The problem is that often only see things from our own biased subjective and limited perspective.

    peace

  21. dazz: What does that mean for moral objectivity?

    Objectivity is only possible if God exists.

    The difference between objective and subjective is the difference between the creature and the creator

    peace

  22. Acartia: Theists always argue that evil is the consequence of the gift of free will that God gave us. Some gift. Because I have the free will to choose between vanilla and chocolate ice cream, millions had to die at the hands of the Nazis. Because I have the free will to choose to buy a Toyota rather than a Ford, millions had to endure slavery.

    You have a skewed idea of free will. Free will does not involve making choices between various pleasures, it means acting out of our inner being without having either an inner or outer compulsion to do so. Free will goes hand in hand with truth and love.

  23. fifthmonarchyman: um because they are moral.

    There is nothing inconsistent with me doing something immoral but God using it for Good. That does not mean my actions are not immoral it just means that there is more than one perspective at play

    You missed the point entirely.

  24. fifthmonarchyman: Objectivity is only possible if God exists.

    The difference between objective and subjective is the difference between the creature and the creator

    That’s pure, unadulterated bullshit

  25. dazz: That’s pure, unadulterated bullshit

    that is just your subjective opinion 😉

    peace

  26. Acartia,

    I don’t understand you. If attributions of good are subjective (which I think is Murray’s view, fwiw), then everybody’s take is as good as everybody else’s. That’s probably the most common use of ‘subjective.’ You think the Holocaust was bad, but that doesn’t make anybody who thinks it was good wrong. Subjectivism puts morality on a par with liking broccoli.

  27. keiths: Of course the free will defense is particularly lame when it comes to dealing with instances of natural evil like the earthquake you mentioned. Would any theists care to tell us why the “freedom” of tectonic plates to kill people, unhindered by God, is such a good thing?

    Steiner gives us this account in The Deed of Christ and the Opposing Spiritual Powers

    But let us not forget that since that time the destiny of Ahriman has been interwoven in a certain sense with the destiny of humanity, and manifold happenings, of which the uninitiated can know nothing, keep the whole karma of humanity in perpetual connection with the karma of Ahriman. To understand what will now be said, we must realize that over and above the karma which belongs to every individual human being, there is at every stage of existence a universal karmic law. All the categories of beings have their karma — the karma of the one differing from that of the other. But karma operates through every realm of existence and there are things in the karma of mankind, in the karma of a people, of a community or other group of human beings, which must be regarded as collective karma, so that in certain circumstances the individual can be drawn into the sway of the collective karma. It will not always be easy for one who cannot penetrate to the root of the matter to discern exactly where the influences of the powers concerned lie in the case of human beings overtaken by such a destiny. An individual within some community may well be entirely guiltless as far as his own karma is concerned; but because he stands within a field of collective karma, calamity may befall him. If, however, he is entirely guiltless, compensation will be made in later incarnations.
    In the wider connection we must look not only at the karma of the past but also think of the karma of the future. A terrible fate may befall a whole group of human beings; the reason why just this group should suffer such a destiny is not to be discovered. Someone who might be capable of investigating the karma of an individual will in certain circumstances be unable to find anything at all that could have led to this tragic fate, for the threads of karma are extremely complicated. The cause of such karmic happenings may lie far, far away — but it is connected with these people nevertheless. And it may be that the whole group, while guiltless, has been overtaken by some collective karma which could not overtake those immediately guilty, because circumstances did not make this possible. In such cases the only thing that can be said is this: In the total karma of an individual, everything is ultimately balanced out, including what befalls him without guilt on his part; it is all inscribed in his karma and compensation in the fullest sense will be made in future time. — Therefore in considering the law of karma we must also take into account the karma of the future. Nor must it be forgotten that man is not an isolated being but that every individual has to share jointly in the collective karma of humanity.

    Here Ahriman can be equated with Satan. Steiner recognises two opposing powers pitted against Christ: They are Lucifer, (the Spirit of Light, the Biblical Devil) and secondly Ahriman, (Satan, Mephistopheles in Goethe’s Faust). These are the Zoroastrian Spirits of light and Spirits of Darkness.

    I am reluctant to go too deeply into Steiner’s spiritual understandings because I know that those who are unable to “park their priors by the door” to his writings will not even try to understand them from an unbiased angle.

  28. dazz: Also, this seems to support my argument that if one is to accept this defense, we should avoid at all cost to exercise our free will: we already have the ability, so if we manage to not use it at all, no evil ensues. If God never desired evil to begin with, that seems the only way to please God

    No one can carry out an evil act in freedom. There is always some compulsion to act in this way, e.g. for personal gain, sadistic pleasure, to cover something up, revenge, that sort of thing. Even acts of kindness and philanthropy are not free acts if they are performed because it gives the actor satisfaction or pleasure. There are very few acts that are done in freedom.

  29. walto:
    Acartia,

    Subjectivism puts morality on a par with liking broccoli.

    Only to a dimwit. Morality is not cuisine. It’s how we respect or don’t respect others (persons, civil society, financial dealings, etc., etc.)

    Walto, why do you need to trivialize things?

  30. Pedant: Only to a dimwit. Morality is not cuisine. It’s how we respect or don’t respect others (persons, civil society, financial dealings, etc., etc.)

    Walto, why do you needto trivialize things?

    I don’t think he’s doing that. It was just an analogy. Actually labeling morality as subjective in principle seems to me like it’s a very good way of trivializing it. I used to think I was a moral subjectivist too, until I learned what that really means

  31. Patrick: Here’s a timeline of when those books were written:

    Can’t you give us THE TIMELINE rather than just A TIMELINE? Why should anyone accept your timeline? Were the books signed and dated by the original authors, is that how you can be so certain?

  32. fifthmonarchyman: The difference between objective and subjective is the difference between the creature and the creator

    keiths seems loathe to admit that he has objective evidence for evil and keiths seems likewise loathe to admit that his evidences for evil are subjective.

    I guess the evidential argument from evil “works for him,” but that’s no reason it ought to work for everyone else.

  33. Patrick: Let’s be very clear here. The discussion isn’t about a god, as no such thing has ever been shown to exist. The discussion is about theists’ claims.

    I’ve already demonstrated that this claim is false.

    If we really can’t even agree on that is being discussed perhaps it’s time for keiths and Patrick to back off, since their insults and rants have nothing to do with the views of the people they disagree with.

  34. keiths: For fun, let’s talk about the God you worship. Is he omniscient? Omnipotent? Omnibenevolent? Omnipresent? Perfectly just?

    When I worship those are not the things that motivate me or come to mind. Let’s not make fun of my worship. ok?

  35. keiths: Vincent, Mung, fifth, Charlie, J-Mac,

    It’s time to put Christianity behind you and face the truth like grownups, guys.

    Perhaps. But when you refuse to answer even the simplest of questions, I don’t see any reason to change my mind about whether or not God exists.

    And you do refuse to answer simple questions. That’s not in dispute.

  36. Pedant:

    Walto, why do you need to trivialize things?

    It’s his go-to strategy when he’s unable to present a persuasive argument.

  37. A god who is “omnibenevolent” would permit no evil. Evil exists. Therefore, no “omnibenevolent” god exists. Looks like the logical problem of evil to me!

Leave a Reply