Feser’s fourth proof and the mystery of existence

If the Aristotelian argument for a purely actual Being (which I critiqued in my previous post) is the backbone of Feser’s five proofs of God’s existence, the Thomistic proof is the beating heart, as it gets to the very core of what God is: Pure Existence itself, according to philosophy Professor Edward Feser. Today, I’m going to argue that this notion of God is utterly nonsensical. But it is not merely the argument’s conclusion which is flawed: the Thomistic proof also rests on shaky foundations, as the real distinction it posits between a finite thing’s essence and its existence is a highly dubious one: the main argument cited in support of it actually points to a matter-form distinction, instead. The second argument for a real distinction between a thing’s essence and its existence establishes nothing of the sort: all it shows is that whatever causes a thing to have existence also causes the nature or essence of that thing. A third argument for the essence-existence distinction illicitly assumes that the term “existence” names a single perfection, which is inherently simple and unlimited.

In addition, Feser’s Thomistic proof trades on an equivocation between the notion of a Being whose essence is identical to its own existence and that of a Being whose essence is Pure Existence – an equivocation which is grounded in the background metaphysical assumption that the concept of “existence” is a simple and unlimited one. In reality, as I shall explain below, the concept of “existence” is neither simple nor complex, neither limited nor unlimited, but rather, indefinite – which is one reason why the attempt to characterize God as Pure Existence, or Being itself, is doomed at the outset. Finally, any attempt to construe God as some sort of activity – whether it be Pure Existence, Pure Actuality, or Thought thinking Itself, or Love loving Himself – is radically mistaken, either because it reifies an abstraction (Existence exists, Actuality acts) or because it generates an infinite regress (Love loves love loves love…). In plain English: We need to think of God first and foremost as a noun, and not merely as a verb – in other words, as an Agent, rather than simply as an unlimited act of thought or love or “be-ing.”

Despite its flawed conception of God, Feser’s Thomistic proof is not without its merits: it highlights the sheer contingency of beings whose nature provides no guarantee of their existence, and it shows that any being whose existence is not explained by its nature cannot be regarded as a self-explanatory being. In so doing, it sets the stage for Feser’s fifth, Rationalist proof, which appeals to the Principle of Sufficient Reason in order to argue that beings which are not self-explanatory require an external cause for their existence, and that there must be an Ultimate Cause for the existence of these contingent beings, which is self-explanatory. However, the Rationalist argument for a necessary, self-explanatory Being, taken by itself, is unable to establish whether this Being possesses intellect and will. In his book, Feser appeals to the notion of a purely actual Being in order to demonstrate that this necessary Being must be intelligent, but I’ve already explained in my previous post why this approach fails. In the end, only Feser’s third, Augustinian proof, which argues for the existence of an Ultimate Mind, has any hope of taking us to a personal Deity. Accordingly, in my next post, I plan to discuss whether Feser’s fifth and third proofs, taken together, can establish the existence of an Ultimate Mind, which explains both its own existence and that of everything else.

==================================================================

MAIN MENU

FESER’S FOURTH, THOMISTIC PROOF: A CRITICAL REVIEW

1. The four tiers of Feser’s Thomistic proof

2. Feser’s arguments for a real distinction between essence and existence, in empirical objects

(a) A preliminary disclaimer

(b) Why does the distinction between “essence” and”existence” matter, and how does it relate to God?

(c) What does Feser mean by “essence” and “existence”?

(d) What does Feser mean by a real distinction?

(e) Feser’s three arguments for a real distinction between essence and existence
(i) Feser’s first argument: I can know what something is, without knowing whether it actually exists
(ii) Feser’s second argument: the contingency of things indicates that their existence does not belong to them by nature
(iii) Feser’s third argument: anything whose essence is its existence would have to be Pure Existence itself

(f) Lack of logico-mathematical notation: a common flaw in all of Feser’s arguments

(g) Formalizing and re-evaluating Feser’s arguments

3. Feser’s argument that there is at least one Being whose essence and existence are identical

4. Feser’s argument for the uniqueness and necessity of the Being whose essence is its own existence

5. Feser’s argument for the pure actuality of the Being whose essence is its own existence

6. A Critical Evaluation of Feser’s Fourth, Thomistic Proof

7. Why I think Aquinas’ and Feser’s claim that God’s essence is Pure Existence implies atheism

8. Another way of thinking about God?

===================================================================

A. FESER’S FOURTH, THOMISTIC PROOF

1. The four tiers of Feser’s Thomistic proof

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

Feser’s Thomistic proof is like a four-tiered wedding cake. Image courtesy of Fandom and Wikia.org.

Feser’s Thomistic proof may be likened to a four-layered wedding cake. At the foundation is the “first layer” of the argument, where Feser sets the scene by arguing for a real distinction between a thing’s essence and a thing’s existence, for the everyday things which we can experience. This corresponds to steps 1 to 11 of his Thomistic argument (2017, pp. 128-131).

The second layer is the one in which Feser attempts to establish that there must be some Ultimate Cause (or causes) in which essence and existence coincide, and which imparts existence to ordinary beings like ourselves, whose essence and existence are distinct. Feser’s arguments in support of this conclusion can be found in steps 12 to 23 of his proof.

The third layer of Feser’s proof is where he argues that this Ultimate Cause, whose essence is Pure Existence, must be a unique and necessary Being, Who sustains everything else in existence. This corresponds to steps 24 to 28 of the proof.

The fourth layer, or top tier, of the Thomistic proof (steps 29 to 36) is where Feser argues that the One Necessary Being must be a Purely Actual Being, which, he claims (citing arguments he has already put forward in his Aristotelian argument in chapter one) entails that this Being “must be immutable, eternal, immaterial, incorporeal, perfect, omnipotent, fully good, intelligent, and omniscient” (step 33). Such a Being, Feser concludes, can only be called God.

That’s Feser’s Thomistic proof in a nutshell. I’m going to begin my critique of Feser’s argument at the foundation, or bottom layer, where Feser endeavors to show that for the ordinary things we experience in the world around us, there is a real distinction between their essence and their act of existence.

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

2. Feser’s arguments for a real distinction between essence and existence, in empirical objects

(a) A preliminary disclaimer

Drawing of a unicorn by Friedrich Johann Justin Bertuch (1747-1822). We can describe the essence of a unicorn, but it does not exist. Thomists would say that a unicorn’s essence is not endowed with existence. Public domain image.

Before I begin my discussion of Feser’s fourth, Thomistic proof of God’s existence, I’d like to begin with a modest disclaimer: I will not be proposing or defending any philosophical theory of what it means for something to exist. That’s because I’m not totally satisfied with any of the existing theories. What I can tell you, from my studies of philosophy, is that no account of “existence” is without its problems. I should also state up-front that although I disagree with Dr. Feser’s account of essence and existence and find fault with the arguments he puts forward for it, it is nevertheless possible that it might turn out to be correct, at least for contingent beings. (On the other hand, I would maintain that Feser’s account of God as Existence Itself isn’t just contentious, but downright nonsensical.)

To illustrate the uncertainty that reigns in the field of philosophy on the question of what “existence” is, I’d like to quote from the first and final paragraphs of the article by Associate Professor Michael Nelson (University of California, Riverside) on Existence, in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:

Existence raises deep and important problems in metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophical logic. Many of the issues can be organized around the following two questions: Is existence a property of individuals? and Assuming that existence is a property of individuals, are there individuals that lack it?

I began by saying that existence raises a number of deep and important problems in metaphysics, philosophy of language, and philosophical logic. I have examined some of those problems and surveyed a number of different accounts of existence. None of the theories surveyed is wholly satisfying and without cost. The first view proposed by Frege and Russell treats existence as a second-order property and assimilates seemingly singular existentials to general existentials. The proposal requires descriptivism, the thesis that ordinary proper names have descriptive equivalences, which many find to be a problematic thesis. The second Meinongian view requires countenancing individuals that do not exist. We have seen the view face challenges in giving coherent and yet informative and compelling individuation principles for nonexistent individuals and all versions of the view suffer from the problem of metaphysical overpopulation. Finally I presented the naive view that existence is a universal property of individuals. That view faced the problem of having to reject the truth of highly intuitively true singular negative existential sentences like ‘Ronald McDonald does not exist’. The view also faces difficulties in properly accounting for the interaction of quantifiers and modal and tense operators. Existence remains, then, itself a serious problem in philosophy of language, metaphysics, and logic and one connected to some of the deepest and most important problems in those areas.

Bearing in mind that the topic of “existence” is a philosophical minefield, let us proceed to carefully examine Feser’s (and Aquinas’) theory of existence.

===================================================================

(b) Why does the distinction between “essence” and “existence” matter, and how does it relate to God?

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

Evolution of Sprite bottles over time. In an analogy below, I liken ordinary things’ essences to bottles of various kinds, and their existence to the Sprite beverage which is poured into them. This is roughly how Thomists view ordinary things. Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

For the benefit of readers who don’t have a background in philosophy, I’d like to propose a simple analogy which I hope will help explain Aquinas’ (and Feser’s) views on essence and existence, and how they point to the existence of God. In a nutshell, Aquinas views the essences of ordinary things (including human beings) as mere vessels or receptacles for their existence, which is poured into them from outside. Things’ essences, considered purely in themselves, are not real: rather, they have the potential to be “real-ized,” just as an empty beverage bottle has the potential to be filled with Sprite. Different kinds of bottles may have different shapes, just as different kinds of things have different forms. Additionally, two bottles of the same shape are composed of different material, just as two things of the same kind contain different matter. Existence is something which things are endowed with, just as Sprite is something which bottles are filled with. But just as empty bottles, considered in themselves, are unable to tell us anything about the mysterious beverage known as Sprite, so too, essences which have a potential to be “real-ized” are incapable of explaining their own reality. And just as the beverage we call Sprite needs no bottle to contain it, so too, Pure and Unlimited Existence needs no separate essence to constrain it: its essence is simply to exist, and nothing more. It is Being Itself. Drawing on Aquinas’s writings, Feser goes on to argue that Pure Existence is unique, that it exists necessarily, and that it’s fully actual, which (he argues) means it’s perfect, omnipotent and omniscient, and deserves to be called God.

No analogy is perfect, however. In order to avoid misunderstandings, I’d like to point out two flaws in the analogy I have proposed. One flaw in the foregoing illustration is that bottles may be filled with different kinds of beverages: for example, Coca Cola, Fanta and orange juice, in addition to Sprite. Existence, however, doesn’t come in different flavors: the only thing, according to Thomists, which differentiates my existence from yours is that my individual essence (as this human being) is distinct from your essence, as that human being. More precisely: even though you and I are two individuals of the same kind (i.e. human beings), my signate matter is distinct from yours, as my flesh and bone is not the same as your flesh and bone. However, Aquinas contends that something which is Pure Existence would contain all perfections, making it rather like an imaginary beverage which somehow contains all flavors within itself.

Another limitation of the foregoing illustration is that the Sprite in a bottle is completely separable from the bottle containing it (e.g. when the bottle is emptied), whereas Feser holds that the essence and existence of an ordinary thing are really distinct but inseparable from one another. How two terms can be really distinct but nonetheless inseparable is a subject we’ll explore below.

===================================================================

(c) What does Feser mean by “essence” and “existence”?

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

The Greek philosopher Aristotle (left) defined the essence or nature of a human being: man, he said, is a rational animal. Centuries later, the Aristotelian philosopher, St. Thomas Aquinas (right) drew a distinction between a man’s essence and his existence
Left: Portrait bust of Aristotle; an Imperial Roman (1st or 2nd century AD) copy of a lost bronze sculpture made by Lysippos. Image courtesy of the Louvre Museum, Eric Gaba and Wikipedia.
Right: image of St. Thomas Aquinas in stained glass, courtesy of Beao and Wikipedia.
———————————

But what exactly is a thing’s essence, anyway? And what do Thomists mean by “existence”? As we’ll see, Feser expresses himself in several contradictory ways, when explaining what a thing’s existence is.

A thing’s essence is defined by Feser as “what it is” (2017, p. 117), or “its very nature” (2017, p. 119), whereas a thing’s existence is defined as “the fact that it is” (2017, pp. 13, 117).

Are essences real?

Let’s begin with essences. The most radical critique that could possibly be directed at Feser’s argument for a real distinction between a thing’s essence and its existence is to deny outright that things have any essences in the first place.

There are philosophers who reject essentialism, or the view that there are essences in the natural world. Nevertheless, it remains a philosophically respectable position, as readers can verify for themselves by perusing Alexander Bird’s article on Natural Kinds in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. A strong case can be made for the assertion that statements like ‘Water is H2O’ and ‘Gold is the element with atomic number 79’ are necessary truths, which specify the essence of some natural kind.

The term “natural kind” has various definitions in the philosophical literature. However, it is generally agreed that (i) the members of a natural kind should have some natural properties in common (e.g. the class of “white objects,” to use one of J.S. Mill’s examples, does not comprise a natural kind, but the class of atoms having an atomic number of 79 does – viz. gold); (ii) natural kinds should permit inductive inferences to be drawn by scientists; (iii) natural kinds can be described by laws of nature; (iv) the members of a natural kind should form a “kind” of some sort; (v) natural kinds should form a hierarchy (e.g. in the field of biology, Linnaeus’s taxonomy provides an especially clear example of such a hierarchy, while in the standard model of quantum physics, the various kinds of fundamental particles (electron, tau neutrino, charm quark) fall into broader categories (lepton, quark), which fall themselves under higher kinds (fermion, boson)); and (vi) natural kinds should be categorically distinct – in other words, there cannot be a smooth transition from one kind to another. Chemistry provides the best example of requirement (vi), insofar as there are no intermediates between neighboring atoms in the periodic table, such as chlorine (element no. 17) and argon (no. 18). The claim that natural kinds have essences is a stronger philosophical claim, but in recent years, an increasingly large number of philosophers have articulately defended this view – notably, Saul Kripke, Hilary Putnam, Brian Ellis (whom Feser quotes in his book), E. J. Lowe, Nancy Cartwright and David Oderberg, author of Real Essentialism (Routledge, 2008), who is also quoted by Feser.

In Aristotle’s day, the world of living things afforded the most obvious evidence for the claim that there are natural kinds, with essential properties. But ever since Darwin demonstrated that species change over the course of time, biological essentialism has become philosophically contentious, and as Bird notes in his article, chemical kinds have now replaced biological kinds as the paradigms of natural kinds. Even so, species essentialism continues to have some notable exponents, and the article on Species in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy even has a special section on what it calls The New Biological Essentialism.

In any case, Feser is not committed to species essentialism: indeed, he even declares (2017, p. 145) that he could happily concede that there are no biological essences, if pressed, while still maintaining that the physical particles which make up material objects have clear-cut essences.

Finally, as Feser points out, citing an argument defended by the philosopher Crawford Elder, the view that all essences are constructs of the human mind is self-refuting, as it would entail that the essence which we call “mind” – whether we think of it as the brain or as something immaterial is irrelevant here – is itself a construct of the mind, which means that the mind is both prior to and posterior to itself. (Of course, this argument assumes that the word “mind” denotes an essence, which a skeptic might question. However, it should be clear from the foregoing remarks that essentialism is alive and well, in philosophical circles.)

What does Feser mean by a thing’s existence?

Feser highlights the distinction between the an object’s essence and its existence by pointing out (in a passage which I’ll discuss below) that “you can know a thing’s essence without knowing whether or not it exists” (2017, p. 118). The phrase “whether or not it exists” would appear to suggest that a thing’s existence is a Boolean data type, with only two possible values: true or false. Alternatively, the phrase, “the fact that it is,” might suggest that a thing’s existence is simply the proposition that it exists. Indeed, Feser’s discussion of human beings in an example he provides on page 117 of his book lends support to this interpretation: he points out that you can know “the nature or essence of a human being” without knowing “that there really are human beings,” which seems to imply that a human being’s existence (as opposed to its essence” is simply the proposition that human beings exist.

But this clearly will not do. For Feser wants to argue that there is one Being – God – in Whom essence and existence are identical. And it is absolutely impossible for a being’s essence to be identical with either a Boolean (true-false) data type or a proposition, no matter what kind of being it is. To equate a being’s essence with a data type or a proposition would be to commit a category mistake, like saying that a joke has wheels or that happiness is four-legged. If having an essence identical with its existence were a defining feature of anything worthy to be called “God,” then Feser’s argument would be tantamount to a proof of atheism – something I am sure he does not intend it to be.

Is there a better way of understanding what Feser means by “existence”? Fortunately, there is: we can consider it as a first-order predicate of individual objects – an interpretation which Feser himself endorses, later on in his book (2017, pp. 135-138). In order to support this interpretation, I’d like to begin by quoting a short passage from Dr. Nelson’s article in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (which I cited above), where he succinctly contrasts Aristotle’s and Aquinas’ views on the question of existence:

Aristotle seems to have seen nothing more to existence than essence; there is not a space between an articulation of what a thing is and that thing’s existing. Saint Thomas Aquinas, on the other hand, famously distinguished a thing’s essence from its existence. Aquinas argued something as follows, in chapter 4 of his On Being and Essence. One can have an understanding of what a man or a phoenix is without knowing whether it exists. So, existence is something in addition to essence. In short, Aquinas argued that existence is a separate property as existence is not part of most objects’s natures and so those objects can be conceived or thought of separately from their existing.

This is roughly correct, but not quite. As Dr. Feser points out in chapter four of his book, Aquinas regarded existence as “a first-order predicate of individual objects” (2017, p. 135), but not as a property of objects:

That we can predicate existence of a thing doesn’t entail that it is a property or other accident, however. It is, from the Thomist’s point of view, not a property or accident, for a thing can have properties or other accidents only if it first exists. (2017, p. 138)

So now we know what Feser means by a thing’s essence and what he means by its existence. Feser, like other Thomists, maintains that there is a real distinction between an entity’s essence and its existence. What does he mean by that?

===================================================================

(d) What does Feser mean by a real distinction?

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

The radius and circumference of a circle are really distinct from one another, despite the fact that each is inseparable from the other. Image courtesy of Optimager and Wikipedia.

In his latest book, Five proofs of the Existence of God (Ignatius Press, 2017), Feser makes it clear that a real distinction is not to be confused with a merely conceptual distinction, but he defines these terms only in passing. A more rigorous treatment of the subject can be found in Feser’s earlier work, Scholastic Metaphysics (editiones scholasticae, 2014, pp. 72-73), where he states that for Thomists, a real distinction “reflects a difference in extra-mental reality,” which “holds entirely apart from the way the intellect conceives of a thing,” whereas a logical distinction is one which “reflects only a difference in [our] ways of thinking about this extra-mental reality.” For example, “individual objects like people, dogs, trees and stones are really distinct,” and the various parts of an individual object are also really distinct. Additionally, there is a real distinction between a thing (e.g. a stone) and its positive accidents (e.g. its color), and there is also a real distinction between the various accidents of a thing (e.g. between a stone’s color and its shape). We can even speak of a real distinction between a thing and its modes – say, between a stone on the one hand and its current location, state of rest or state of motion on the other – even though the latter has no being apart from the former. (Feser’s thinking on this subject follows that of Aristotle, who placed a thing in the category of substance, and its location in the category of place – see here for Professor Taylor Marshall’s excellent summary of Aristotle’s ten categories. Writing 2,000 years before the advent of Newtonian physics, Aristotle had no category for a thing’s state of motion, but it strikes me as entirely reasonable, and broadly in keeping with Aristotle’s ontology, to create an eleventh category, in order to accommodate this concept.)

As an example of a conceptual or logical distinction, Feser provides several illustrations: the purely verbal distinction between a bachelor and an unmarried man (2017, p. 117), or between “human being” and “rational animal” (2014, p. 73), or the somewhat stronger, virtual distinction between a man’s rationality and his animality (2014, p. 74), which coincide in human beings, but which can nevertheless be mentally considered in isolation from one another, even in creatures like ourselves. I find the last example puzzling, however, as Feser elsewhere declares: “The essence of human beings, rational animality, has rationality and animality as parts” (2014, p. 246). I would have thought it obvious if A and B are parts of C, then the distinction between A and B is a real one. But let that pass.

In both his earlier work, Scholastic Metaphysics (editiones scholasticae, 2014) and his recent book, Five proofs of the Existence of God (Ignatius Press, 2017), Feser insists that a real distinction between A and B does not imply their separability, and he cites an example provided by the metaphysician, David Oderberg: the radius and circumference of a circle are obviously really distinct from one another, since the latter is two pi times the former; nevertheless, they are inseparable, for it is impossible for a circle to have a radius without having a circumference, or vice versa.

Now that we understand what Feser means by essence, existence and a real distinction, we are finally in a position to critically evaluate his arguments that there is indeed a real distinction between a contingent being’s essence and its existence.

===================================================================

(e) Feser’s three arguments for a real distinction between essence and existence

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

Very briefly, Feser’s three arguments for a real distinction between an ordinary thing’s essence and its existence can be summarized as follows. First, I can know what something is, without knowing whether anything of that kind actually exists. For instance, the Thylacine (also known as the Tasmanian tiger or marsupial wolf) is an animal whose natural characteristics have been extensively studied and described by scientists, but whose existence remains the subject of lively dispute: despite the fact that it is supposed to have died out in 1936, there are many people who claim to have seen it in recent years. Second, the contingency of material things, or the fact that they can come to be and pass away, indicates that their existence does not belong to them by nature. The dodo, for instance, died out 350 years ago. Third, if there were something whose essence and existence were identical, then that thing would have to be something whose essence just is existence itself. Obviously, there cannot be two such things; hence, if the essence and existence of ordinary things is identical, then we are forced to accept the radical thesis that there is only one thing in the entire cosmos (Monism), which Feser takes to be a philosophically absurd position. I will discuss these and other arguments put forward by Feser for a real distinction between essence and existence, below.

===================================================================

(i) Feser’s first argument: I can know what something is, without knowing whether it actually exists

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

A life restoration of the largest known specimen of a pterodactyl. Feser contends that because I can know what a pterodactyl is without knowing whether such creatures still exist, a thing’s “whatness” or essence must be really distinct from its existence. Image courtesy of Matthew Martyniuk and Wikipedia.

Feser’s first argument for a real distinction between essence and existence is that I can know what a thing is, without knowing whether it is:

Consider first that you can know a thing’s essence without knowing whether or not it exists. Suppose a person had, for whatever reason, never heard of lions, pterodactyls, or unicorns. Suppose you gave him a detailed description of the natures of each. You then tell him that of the three creatures, one exists, one used to exist but is now extinct, and the third never existed, and you ask him to tell you which is which given what he now knows about their essences, he would of course be unable to do so. But then the existence of the creatures that do exist must be really distinct from their essences, otherwise one could know of their existence merely from knowing their essences… [I]f the essence and existence of a thing were not distinct features of reality, knowing the former should suffice for knowing the latter, yet it doesn’t. (2017, p. 118)

Does Feser’s argument work at the individual level?

While Feser’s argument initially appears quite plausible when we consider the essence of a thing (say, a pterodactyl) at the generic or specific levels, it fails altogether at the individual level. I cannot know what a particular thing is, without at the same time knowing that it is. This is important, because as we have seen, Feser regards existence as a first-order predicate of individual objects. That being the case, it is very odd that we are unable to distinguish our knowledge of an individual thing’s essence (or what-ness) from our knowledge of its existence (or that-ness).

Now, I imagine that Feser may attempt to respond at this point with a counter-example. In his book, The Last Superstition (St. Augustine’s Press, 2008) he illustrates his claim that there’s nothing about an essence which guarantees its existence, with the aid of an example involving three individuals, one dead, one living and one fictional: Socrates, George Bush and the Batman character Bruce Wayne (2008, pp. 103-104). But in the case of the fictional character Bruce Wayne, we know who he is, either (a) by way of a general description – e.g. a wealthy American playboy, philanthropist, and owner of Wayne Enterprises, who, after witnessing the murder of his parents as a child, swore vengeance against criminals – which still does not get to the heart of the individual’s true “whatness,” as it only holds true of that individual contingently, or (b) by way of reference to other fictional particulars – e.g. the son of Dr. Thomas Wayne and Martha Wayne – whose identity remains undefined. So I think Feser’s fictional example is an unconvincing one. There is no true sense in which I can know an individual’s “whatness” without knowing that he exists. There are of course individuals whose historicity remains disputed: Biblical scholars disagree as to whether Moses was a real person, for instance. But even here, it should be apparent that we remain unacquainted with these individuals’ true “whatness,” and are forced to substitute a general description in its place – which is the very reason why these individuals’ existence remains a contentious issue.

Two types of knowledge: why Feser’s argument fails at the specific level

Even if at the specific level, however, what Feser’s argument for a real distinction between essence and existence overlooks is that there is a profound difference between knowing what something is, and knowing that [or whether] some proposition is true. The former kind of knowledge relates to the meaning of a term (e.g. “pterodactyl”), whereas the latter kind of knowledge relates to the truth of a statement about that term (e.g. “Pterodactyls exist.”) The fact that I can know what a pterodactyl is, without knowing whether it is, does not entail that there is some difference between its “whatness” and its existence; rather, all it implies is that “knowing what” and “knowing whether” are different, and that a term is not the same as a statement, or proposition containing that term.

In short: what Feser’s argument points to is a distinction between two types of knowledge – knowing what and knowing that – rather than a distinction between two metaphysical parts of an ordinary thing.

How Feser should argue for a real distinction between essence and existence, and why it won’t work

Supposing (hypothetically) there were indeed a real distinction between a thing’s essence and its existence, what would a good argument for such a distinction look like? Let’s consider Feser’s case of pterodactyls. An argument which established that I could know what a pterodactyl is, without knowing what a pterodactyl’s existence is, would indeed point to a real distinction between a pterodactyl’s essence and its existence. But in fact there is no such argument: to know what a pterodactyl is is simply to know its unique form of existence, with all its possibilities and constraints. And even if pterodactyls had never existed, we would still grasp what it would mean for them to exist, simply by grasping their natures.

What Feser’s argument actually establishes: a real distinction between matter and form, rather than between essence and existence

At this point, an Aristotelian critic might object: even if we needed to invoke a real distinction in order to explain the fact that I can know what a pterodactyl is, without knowing whether it still exists, the distinction in question would not be an essence-existence distinction, but a form-matter distinction. On the Aristotelian-Thomistic view of the intellect, whenever I grasp the concept of a pterodactyl, my intellect receives its substantial form, abstracted from the signate matter of any particular entity which happens to instantiate the form in question. Because my intellect receives a form abstracted from matter, it cannot know, simply by understanding what this form is, whether or not anything exists in Nature which possesses this form. That alone is enough to explain how I can know what a thing is, without knowing whether it exists. There is no need to postulate an additional distinction between a thing’s essence and its act of existence.

(Note: An argument along these lines was first put forward by the philosopher David Twetten, in his 2006 paper, Really Distinguishing Essence from esse, in Proceedings of the Society for Medieval Logic and Metaphysics 6:57-94. Twetten considers this argument to be a strong one, but he also thinks a Thomist can answer it, as we’ll see below.)

An objection from Feser: form and matter cannot explain the actual existence of an object

In his work, Scholastic Metaphysics (editiones scholasticae, 2014) Feser argues that the form-matter distinction is incapable of accounting for the actual existence of ordinary things. Summarizing an argument first developed by David Twetten in 2006 and formulated independently by Feser in a 2011 paper, Feser responds to the Aristotelian objection above, as follows:

To avoid acknowledging that there is a real distinction between a thing’s essence and existence, the imagined Aristotelian critic will have to be able to account for a material thing’s being actual in terms of its essence – that is, its matter and form – alone. But its matter alone cannot be what accounts for it, since matter by itself is pure potency and thus cannot account for actuality. Nor can its form alone be what accounts for it, since on an Aristotelian view form is not actual in the first place apart from matter. Furthermore, form alone cannot account even for a material thing’s continued actuality once it comes into being, for if it could do so, it would continue in being after the substance of which it is the form was destroyed (which on an Aristotelian view it does not). Nor can the substance comprising form and matter together account for its own actuality, since this really amounts to the form, qua what actualizes the matter so as to make a substance, being the explanation of the actuality of the whole – which, for the reasons just given, cannot be the case. So, there must be something really distinct from a thing’s form and matter, and thus really distinct from its essence, that accounts for its actuality. (2014, p. 249)

“The Anatomy Lesson of Dr. Nicolaes Tulp” by Rembrandt van Rijn (1632). Mauritshuis, Amsterdam. Image courtesy of The Yorck Project and Wikipedia. According to Thomists, living things have a single substantial form, which grounds all of their natural properties. This form departs when a living thing dies. The only thing a corpse has in common with the living thing it once was is prime matter, or pure passive potency, as Thomists describe it. Such a view fails to explain why a corpse has the same shape, size and weight as the living body it once was, despite not having any form in common with the living body. Other Scholastic philosophers argued that the form of a living thing is superimposed on top of the underlying form of a corporeal thing, and that the latter form remains after death, accounting for the physical similarities between a living thing and its corpse.

Now, I could contest certain points in the foregoing argument – for instance, Feser’s assertion that “matter by itself is pure potency.” A Thomist would agree with that, but it is doubtful whether Aristotle would have done so. Even among Scholastic philosophers, the claim that prime matter is utterly devoid of any actuality is a contentious one: Scotists and Suarezians deny it, and Thomists, who uphold it, are forced to accept the absurd view that when an animal dies, its corpse has absolutely nothing in common with the animal it once was, except for pure passive potency – which fails to explain why the corpse has the same shape, size and weight as the original animal.

Nor can I see why the claim that form and matter together account for a thing’s actuality should entail that form alone can account for a thing’s actuality. Feser thinks this follows because form actualizes matter. I would contend that Feser has been misled by his own woolly terminology: the term “account for” is a vague one. If we simply say that anything which is a composite of form and matter actually exists, then we are saying something which is trivially true, on an Aristotelian account. Such a claim in no way entails the outlandish claim that anything which is a form without matter actually exists.

However, it appears to me that Feser’s argument is marred by a more fundamental flaw. Feser seems to be arguing as follows:

1. If there is no real distinction between a material thing’s essence (i.e. its form plus its matter) and its existence, then a thing’s essence must be able to account for its existence.
2. However, a material thing’s essence is unable to account for its existence – regardless of whether we consider form alone, matter alone, or the composite of form and matter.
3. Therefore, there is a real distinction between a material thing’s essence and its existence.

The argument is valid, but I would reject the first premise as false. What we should say instead is:

1(b): if there is no real distinction between a material thing’s essence and its existence, then whatever accounts for a material thing’s existence also accounts for its essence, and vice versa.

I see no reason why an Aristotelian would have any problem accepting premise 1(b), since it applies to individual essences, which are composed of form and signate matter – for instance, an actual lion consists of the universal form of a lion, realized in this flesh and these bones. And there is nothing problematic in someone’s holding that whatever accounts for the existence of this lion also accounts for its essence, as an individual of that species. [By contrast, the universal essence of a lion consists of “matter in general,” or common matter, plus its universal form.]

Immaterial intelligences: a problem for the traditional Aristotelian view?

Dante and Beatrice gaze upon the highest Heaven, the Empyrean. From Gustave Doré’s illustrations to the Divine Comedy, Paradiso Canto 28, lines 16–39. Public domain image from Alighieri, Dante; Cary, Henry Francis (ed) (1892) “Canto XXXI” in The Divine Comedy by Dante, Illustrated, Complete, London, Paris & Melbourne. Courtesy of Wikipedia. Feser argues in his Scholastic Metaphysics that immaterial intelligences, such as angels, constitute a difficulty for the traditional Aristotelian view that a thing’s essence is identical to its existence. Aristotle didn’t believe in angels, of course, but he did believe that immaterial beings moved the heavenly spheres.

Feser briefly raises another argument against his imagined Aristotelian critic, in his Scholastic Metaphysics (editiones scholasticae, 2014): namely, that the form-matter distinction fails to explain how immaterial intelligences, which are composed of form alone, could possibly exist (2014, p. 248). Aristotle himself believed in the reality of such intelligences. However, there is a very good reason why Feser does not mention this argument in his more recent work, Five Proofs of the Existence of God (Ignatius Press, 2017): namely, that to do so would be question-begging. For what Feser is attempting to establish, in his Thomistic proof of the existence of God, is that “the essences of things of our experience must be distinct from the existence of those things” (2017, p. 119). Since we are material beings, we can have no experience of immaterial intelligences.

The incompleteness of our ideas of non-existent objects

A phoenix depicted in a book of legendary creatures by FJ Bertuch (1747–1822). Below, I argue that there is no essence of a phoenix: our concept of a phoenix is only skin-deep. Public domain image from Friedrich Justin Bertuch, Bilderbuch für Kinder (Eigenbesitz), Fabelwesen (1806). Courtesy of Wikipedia.

Another objection to the traditional Aristotelian view raised by Feser is that it fails to account for the essences of imaginary creatures, such as phoenixes and unicorns. As Feser puts it:

Unicorns, if they existed, would be composites of form and matter. Yet they don’t exist. Thus the existence of things that do exist must be something added to their form and matter. (2014, p. 248)

However, it is doubtful whether we actually have any proper concepts of non-existent kinds of objects. (When I say “kinds,” I mean natural kinds; arithmetical and geometrical objects, such as numbers and shapes, are of no concern to me here.) At first blush, the question might appear ridiculous: after all, don’t we all have a clear and distinct idea what a unicorn is? Actually, we don’t. A clear image is not the same thing as a clear idea, or concept, as any good Aristotelian could tell you. Our concept of a unicorn, like that of a winged horse or for that matter, a phoenix, is only skin-deep: we have no idea of how these creatures are supposed to develop, or of their internal anatomy (for example, what is a unicorn’s horn made of, and does it grow back if you cut it off?) Our only complete ideas, it seems, are of actually existent objects – or at the very least, objects which have actually existed at some time (such as mammoths).

Even with long-extinct creatures (such as dinosaurs), our concepts of these creatures are fragmented and incomplete, owing to the fact that we only have their bones (and recently, impressions of their skin as well), but not their skin collagen, let alone their DNA.

What I am proposing, in short, is that the only way to have a complete concept of any kind of entity is by making or discovering one, and that the ideas we have of imaginary creatures (such as unicorns and phoenixes) are actually parasitic on our fully fleshed-out concepts of actually existent creatures. A thing has to actually exist, at some time, in order for it to have a true essence.

===================================================================

(ii) Feser’s second argument: the contingency of things indicates that their existence does not belong to them by nature

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

Lion at a South African waterhole. The existence of lions is a contingent fact, as Feser correctly points out. Image courtesy of Bernard Dupont and Wikipedia.

Feser’s second argument for a real distinction between a material thing’s essence and its existence is that material things are contingent, whereas if their existence were identical to their nature, then they would exist by virtue of their nature, which is manifestly false:

A second reason why the essences of the things of our experience must be distinct from the existence of those things has to do with their contingency – the fact that, though they do exist, they could have failed to exist. For example, lions exist, but had the history of life gone differently, they would not have existed; and it is possible that lions could someday go extinct. Now, if the existence of a contingent thing was not really distinct from its essence, then it would have existence just by virtue of its essence. (2017, p. 119)

The last sentence, as it stands, makes no logical sense: if a contingent thing’s essence is identical to its existence, then all that follows is that for a contingent thing to have an essence is identical to that thing’s having existence. However, it does not follow that the thing in question is necessary (contrary to our initial stipulation that it is contingent); that conclusion would only follow if a thing’s essence were in some way necessary. Feser has given us no reason to think that a thing’s essence is necessary, in his Thomistic argument for the existence of God.

The force of Feser’s second argument can be blunted by freely granting that the existence of contingent things requires a cause (or causes) of some sort. But by the same token, that cause could equally be said to generate things’ natures. Feser writes as if the natures were already there, in some shadowy “potential” realm, just waiting to have the fire of existence “breathed into” them – a supposition which begs the question by assuming at the outset that the two are distinct.

Henry of Ghent’s view: things’ essences require an explanation, too

The medieval philosopher Henry of Ghent (1217-1293) argued that a contingent being’s act of existence (in Latin, esse) is not something added to its nature; rather, the thing itself, in its very essence, can only be explained by its ultimate cause, which keeps it in being. For Henry, this Ultimate Cause was of course God. David Twetten (2006) summarizes this view as follows:

For Henry, no creature has esse [the act of being – VJT] considered absolutely in itself, but only insofar as it is considered in relation to its ultimate cause — as an effect and as a likeness of the divine esse. Therefore, ‘to be’ is not something added as though to something else that already is, but is simply the creature itself insofar as it is related as an effect to the divine essence in the order of efficient causality, just as essence is the creature itself as related by way of likeness to the divine essence in the order of formal causality. To exist, Henry would say, is simply for a thing to be posited outside its causes. (2006, p. 91)

However, Twetten rejects this proposal, on the grounds that it makes a thing’s very identity relative to that of its cause. Following the Scholastic philosopher Suárez, he thinks that this would relativize God’s existence, too:

No less than the greatest critic of the Real Distinction [between essence and existence – VJT], Francisco Suárez, has shown the inadequacy of this alternative, however. To say of a thing ‘it is’ predicates not something relative but something ‘absolute’ of the thing, observes Suárez. Otherwise, to say that God is would also be to introduce a relation to a cause. It remains that if we must account for ‘actually to be’ by something other than form, ‘actually to be’ must be a really distinct component intrinsic to things that are. (2006, p. 91)

I have to say that Suárez’s argument strikes me as a total non sequitur. If there is an Uncaused Being, then by definition, its essence cannot be defined in relation to any cause. There is no contradiction in defining the essence (or identity) of a material thing in relation to that of its cause, while maintaining that an Uncaused Cause (whatever it may be) possesses an essence in an absolute, non-relative manner. For theists, of course, this Uncaused Cause will be God Himself; for atheists and pantheists, it will presumably be some ultimate level of physical reality. Thus of God, theists can not only say, “In Him we live and move and have our being” (Acts 17:28), but also, “In Him we live and move and have our identity.” Thomists seem to be insisting that the identity (or essence) of things can be defined independently of their relation to their Ultimate Cause – which strikes me as a very odd position for a theist to take.

Where do essences come from?

What I am suggesting, in other words, is that Thomists don’t take the Christian doctrine of creation ex nihilo seriously enough. Instead of saying that God made all creatures out of absolutely nothing, they seem to reduce God’s creative activity to endowing some shadowy essences with existence, thereby making them real. But that only begs the question: where did the essences come from?

St. Augustine’s famous answer to this question was that universals (including the idea of a lion) exist in the Mind of God – a solution which Feser discusses in chapter three of his book, and which will be the subject of my next post, in which I’ll evaluate his proof of God’s existence. (It is interesting to note, in passing, that St. Augustine himself saw no need to posit an essence-existence distinction, in order to explain why some of God’s ideas have actually existent counterparts, while others do not.) But even this picture does not go far enough: it suggests an image of God as an artist, playing around with different concepts of beings that He could create, and then picking a subset, and saying: “Right. I’ll create these ones; the rest I don’t need in the world I’ve chosen to make.” Rather, what a theistic philosopher should say is that God decides to “flesh out” a concept, making it complete in every detail, only when He decides to create actually existent things which instantiate that concept. Or putting it in modern terminology: essence does not precede existence, even logically; rather, the two go hand-in-hand.

To be fair, I would like to acknowledge that Feser’s second argument for a real distinction between essence and existence contains a significant metaphysical insight: namely, that contingent things’ natures do not explain their existence, and that some external cause is needed to do so – a point I’ll address at further length in my next post, when I examine Feser’s fifth, Rationalist Proof of God’s existence. Even so, it does not follow that contingent beings’ natures and existences are distinct from one another. “A cannot explain B” does not entail that A is really distinct from B; all it shows is that if they are the same, then B cannot be self-explanatory. God is the Author of the nature and existence of contingent things: the two are not really distinct, after all.

===================================================================

(iii) Feser’s third argument: anything whose essence is its existence would have to be Pure Existence itself

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

Feser’s background metaphysical assumptions – and where they spring from

In order to appreciate Feser’s third argument for a real distinction between a thing’s essence and its existence, we need to grasp certain metaphysical assumptions Feser makes about existence, which he never takes the trouble to spell out in his book. Indeed, I had to go back to his earlier work, Aquinas (Oneworld Publications, Oxford, 2009), to find a clear statement of them.

The first of these assumptions is that existence, considered in itself, is something simple; and the second is that existence, considered in itself, is unlimited. On this picture, what limits and fragments existence are the various receptacles into which it is poured: the essences of things. Without any such receptacle, a thing’s existence would be utterly unbounded, and free from all limitations.

The reason why Feser endorses these metaphysical assumptions is that he views existence as a perfection, as he acknowledges in a passage on Aquinas’ famous Fourth Way of proving God’s existence:

In particular, he [Aquinas] holds that in general (and not just with respect to being or existence) things that have some perfection only to various limited degrees must not have that perfection as part of their essence, “for if each one were of itself competent to have it, there would be no reason why one should have it more than another” (QDP 3.5). That is to say, if it were part of a thing’s very essence to have the perfection, then there would be no reason not to possess it in an unlimited way. (Hence any human being is fully human, which follows from humanity being part of his or her essence, but does not have being to the fullest extent – which would be possible only for something whose essence just is being – or goodness to the fullest extent – which would be possible only for something in some sense having within it every perfection – and so forth.) So, for a limited thing to have some perfection, it must derive it from something outside it

But if the ultimate cause is unlimited in goodness, truth, nobility, or whatever other transcendental we are starting with, then (as we have already said) given the convertibility of the transcendentals it will also have to be unlimited in being and therefore just be pure being or existence itself. (2009, p. 109)

According to Feser, Aquinas holds that for any perfection – and not just existence – if a thing possesses it as part of its essence, then it must possess to to an unlimited degree. Clearly, by implication, existence is a perfection, for Feser. Existence is distinguished from other perfections by being a transcendental, which Feser defines as “something above every genus, common to all beings and thus not restricted to any category or individual” (2009, p. 33).

A third generation Toyota Century at the 2017 Tokyo Motor Show. The Toyota Century is a luxury car, which is often used by the Imperial House of Japan, the Prime Minister of Japan, senior Japanese government leaders, and high-level executive businessmen. Thomists hold that “existence” is a perfection, in addition to all of the other features which make a luxury car great. Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

What is odd about the foregoing passage is that it treats existence as a perfection which a being possesses, in addition to the other perfections it has, instead of simply viewing those perfections as various forms of existence. As a former philosophy lecturer of mine, Professor Bill Ginnane (1929-2007), used to point out, it would be very strange if someone were to list the perfections that a good car should possess – for example, a 5.0 litre V12 engine, double wishbone suspension, an infotainment display, a WiFi hotspot, heated seats and steering wheel, automatic headlamps, and remote keyless entry [I’ve updated his list of features from the 1980s, when I heard him lecture] – and then add existence as another perfection. And it would be even stranger if that person were to then declare that existence was the greatest perfection a car could possess, and that all of the other perfections were of infinitely less importance. To be sure, as Feser would point out, a car is not a natural object but an artifact, but ask yourself this: would it sound any less strange if we were to list the perfections which a good lion should possess, and then add existence as the greatest of them all?

It should be clear from the foregoing passage that Feser regards being or existence as an unlimited perfection; however, the reader may still be wondering why he regards it as a simple one. What is there to prevent a perfection from being complex? The answer is that a transcendental perfection such as being is devoid of all potentiality, considered in itself; whereas if it had parts, these parts would have the potential to come together or to separate.

Let us now return to Aquinas’ argument (quoted by Feser above) that things which possess some perfection only to a limited degree must not have that perfection as part of their essence, “for if each one were of itself competent to have it, there would be no reason why one should have it more than another” (QDP 3.5). The flaw in this argument, as I see it, is that it fails to distinguish between the concepts “unlimited” and “complete.” A thing which has some perfection essentially possesses it completely, but that does not mean that it possesses it to an unlimited degree.

Another distinction which Aquinas fails to draw is that between “indefinite” and “infinite” (or unlimited). In and of itself, the bare concept of “existence” is neither limited nor unlimited, but rather, indefinite. To say that a thing exists does not tell us anything at all about that thing.

The fact that the concept of existence is indefinite also explains why it is devoid of any potentiality. Aquinas attempts to infer from this fact that existence is something inherently simple; but what we should say is that existence, per se, is neither simple nor complex: it is inherently undetermined.

Feser’s anti-monistic argument for a real distinction between essence and existence

Image of a base jump from Earth, courtesy of Christophe Michot and Wikipedia. Feser’s third argument for a real distinction between essence and existence makes a huge and unwarranted logical leap from “There is a being whose essence is identical with its own act of existence” to “There is a being whose essence just is existence itself.” The latter does not follow from the former.

And now, at last, we are in a position to grasp Feser’s third and final argument for a real distinction between essence and existence, which is that identifying the two would entail the radical thesis that there is only one thing in the entire cosmos (Monism). Feser takes this conclusion to be a reductio ad absurdum, and I agree that if his argument worked, it would be.

In his informal statement of the argument, Feser reasons as follows:

A third reason why the essence and existence of each of the things we know through experience must be distinct is that if there is something whose essence and existence are not really distinct – and we will see presently that there is and indeed must be such a thing – then there cannot in principle be more than one such thing. For consider that, if some thing’s essence and existence are not really distinct, then they are identical; and if they are identical in that thing, then that thing would be something whose essence just is existence itself. (2017, p. 120)

As it stands, this argument contains a glaring non sequitur, which undermines the cogency of Feser’s case. It is by no means apparent why a being whose essence and existence are identical would have to be something “whose essence just is existence itself.” All that follows is that the essence of such a being would be identical with its own act of existence. As we shall see below, this non sequitur causes Feser’s entire proof to collapse, in its later stages.

We can make some sense of this apparent lapse of logic on Feser’s part by recalling his remarks above on perfections. As we saw, Feser holds that any being which possesses a perfection as part of its essence, possesses it fully. Thus any human being is fully human; and likewise, anything whose essence is being itself is fully a being, containing within its nature every perfection.

That is Feser’s underlying thinking, but it still doesn’t really answer our question, as it assumes (without justification) that “existence” is a single perfection. Then and only then would it follow that a being whose essence is identical to its existence is a being “whose essence just is existence itself.”

Why Feser maintains that there can only be one being which is existence itself

Above: images of two individuals of different species. Following Aquinas, Feser argues that if “existence” were a common genus to which they both belonged, then the specific difference between them would have to be something other than “existence” – which is impossible.
Left: A photo of The Thinker by Rodin located at the Musée Rodin in Paris. Courtesy of Andrew Horne and Wikipedia.
Right: Chimpanzee named “Gregoire,” born in 1944 and photographed in 2006 at the age of 62, at the Jane Goodall sanctuary of Tchimpounga in Congo Brazzaville. Courtesy of Delphine Bruyère and Wikipedia.
———————————

Next, Feser attempts to show that there cannot be more than one thing that just is existence itself. For if there were two such beings (let’s call them A and B), what could possibly differentiate them?

There are only two possibilities. A and B might be differentiated in the way two species of the same genus are differentiated; or they might be differentiated in the way two members of the same species are differentiated…

…[F]or our imagined things A and B to differ as species do, we would have to regard being that which just is existence itself as a genus, and A and B as two species within that genus; and we’d then have to identify some “specific difference” that A has that makes it a different species of being that which just is existence itself from the species B. But the trouble is that if A has such a “specific difference”, then it will not be that which just is existence itself; rather, it will be that which just is existence itself PLUS that specific difference

Consider now the way two members of the same species are differentiated… [T]hough Socrates and Plato are both human, they can differ because Socrates is humanity plus this particular bit of matter, whereas Plato is humanity plus that other particular bit of matter; and something similar can be said for the different members of other species. But then it should be obvious why we cannot differentiate two things A and B each of which is that which just is existence itself in the way that different members of a species are differentiated. For so differentiated, A and B will not after all be that which just is existence itself; rather, A will be that which just is existence itself PLUS this particular bit of matter, and B will be that which just is existence itself PLUS that other, particular bit of matter… (2017, pp. 120-121)

Is there a third possibility, perhaps? Could there be something for which existence is part of its essence, at least? But as Feser points out (2017, p. 122), that won’t work either: the existence of this being would then depend on its existence, making existence the true essence of this thing.

In general, Feser argues, in order for there to be more than one being which is Pure Existence itself, there would have to be something that made this instance of Pure Existence different from that instance. And then each such being would be a composite of Pure Existence PLUS some differentiating factor – in which case, it would no longer (contrary to our supposition) be Pure Existence.

What Feser’s argument manages to establish

Before I proceed to criticize Feser’s argument, I’d like to point out what he gets right. First, I think his argument that “existence” cannot be construed as a common genus is a cogent one; second, I think his argument that existence cannot be construed as a species is equally cogent. However, I dispute the inference that two entities belonging to the same genus (or for that matter, to the same species), cannot both be identical with their own individual acts of existence. That conclusion only follows if we assume, with Feser, that the term “existence” names a single perfection, which is inherently simple and unlimited. It is precisely this assumption which I think needs to be questioned.

An objection: Could a thing’s existence be composite?

Above: Busts of Socrates and Plato, kept in the Louvre museum and Capitoline museum. Images courtesy of Eric Gaba, Marie-Lan Nguyen and Wikipedia.
———————————

Feser neglects to consider the possibility that a thing’s existence may be composite. In that case, even if two things do belong to the same species or genus, each of them could still be identical with its own act of existence. For instance, consider two individuals, Socrates and Plato, of the same species (in this case, humanity). Socrates is humanity plus this piece of matter, M, while Plato is humanity plus that piece of matter, N. Humanity is their common form, but their essences as individuals are compounds of humanity plus M and humanity plus N, respectively. In that case, why should we not say that Socrates’ existence is likewise a compound of humanity plus M, while Plato’s existence is a compound of humanity plus N?

It seems to me that the reason why Feser is unwilling to entertain this possibility is because of his background metaphysical assumptions: he regards existence (or being) as a transcendental, without any limitations of its own. Because a thing’s existence, per se, is not limited or fragmented, Feser rejects the very notion of a thing whose existence is inherently composite, as unintelligible. His entire argument is predicated on the assumption that a thing’s existence is inherently simple. But it would be a mistake to draw this conclusion about the existence of individual things from the fact that the general concept of “existence” is not a complex one. Rather, what we should say is that “existence per se” is neither limited nor unlimited, and neither simple nor complex, but indefinite: it has no features of its own. As we’ll see below in section 7, this way of looking at things has some very significant implications regarding the classical concept of God.

A second objection: could two things whose essence is identical to their own existence be completely different from one another, like chalk and cheese?

There is another possibility which Feser has neglected to consider, in his argument. Even if one were to grant that no two things belonging to the same species or genus can possibly be identical with their own acts of existence, Feser has overlooked the possibility that two beings whose essences are identical with their own existence may not belong to any common category at all – be it a species, genus or whatever. Why should we assume that if there are two beings whose essence is identical to their existence, then they must belong either to the same species or the same genus? Why couldn’t they be as metaphysically different as chalk and cheese – or even more so, since chalk and cheese are both material substances?

Feser might reply that if there were two things, X and Y, such that X is identical to X’s existence while Y is identical to Y’s existence, then they must surely share something in common (“existence”), as well as having several distinguishing features, which would (a) fall outside the scope of “existence” (what are they then?) and (b) introduce composition into the X’s and Y’s natures, requiring them to have an external cause. But the underlying assumption of this argument is a flawed one: X and Y don’t need to share anything in common at all. They may not belong to any common species or genus; the resemblance between them may be purely analogical. For instance, we could say that an analogy of proportionality holds between them: the relation of X to X’s existence is the same as that of Y to Y’s existence (namely, that of identity).

===================================================================

Are there any other good arguments for a real distinction between essence and existence?

(a) Potency and act

In his Scholastic Metaphysics (editiones scholasticae, 2014), Feser puts forward several arguments for a real distinction between an ordinary thing’s essence and its existence, two of which are not covered in his more recent work, Five Proofs of the Existence of God (Ignatius Press, 2017). I’ll discuss these arguments briefly. The first argument is very straightforward:

The distinction between potency and act must, as the Thomist argues (for reasons set out in chapter 1), be a real distinction. But essence is a kind of potency and existence is a kind of act. Therefore the distinction between essence and existence is a real distinction. (2014, p. 242)

This argument is formally valid; however, I would contest its second premise. If it were indeed true that a thing’s essence is something which is able to be endowed with existence, then the distinction between the two would indeed be a real one. What I have been arguing is that this picture is false: what we should say instead is that neither a thing’s essence nor its existence are self-explanatory, and that the Cause of a thing’s nature (namely, God) is also the cause of its existence.

(b) An ontological argument reductio: why aren’t velociraptors real?

Feser asks: if a thing’s essence is the same as its existence, then why aren’t velociraptors real? Image courtesy of Dino Crisis Wiki and Artwork0.

Another argument for a real distinction between essence and existence, mentioned in passing by Feser, is that without such a distinction, it would follow that the essences of things not only exist, but exist necessarily, which is absurd:

If the existence of a lion, velociraptor or unicorn were not really distinct from its essence, then we should be able to argue, after the fashion of the ontological argument, that lions, velociraptors, and unicorns would exist necessarily rather than contingently, if they exist at all – which is absurd. (2014, p. 244)

This argument assumes that a thing’s essence is somehow necessary – for if it were not, then its existence would not be necessary, either. However, I see no reason to believe that essences are in any sense necessary. Indeed, on a theistic view, we can see why they must be radically contingent. For if essences originate as ideas entertained in the Mind of God (on the Scholastic realist view which Feser defends in chapter three of his book, Five Proofs of the Existence of God, when presenting his Augustinian proof of God’s existence), then it follows that if God had not chosen to entertain these ideas, they would have no reality whatsoever. To hold that these essences must be real in some sense is to hold that God necessarily has the ideas which he has, and that He has no control over the content of His ideas. Such a view is, to say the very least, contentious: it needs to be argued for.

Even if we were to suppose that God must have the concepts which He has, we could still explain why some essences (e.g. that of a velociraptor) are not currently instantiated, simply by invoking Aristotle’s form-matter distinction. On the Aristotelian-Scholastic view, things are not just forms, but composites of form and matter. Since God’s intellect contains the substantial forms of things, abstracted from their matter, it does not follow, from the mere fact that God understands what the form of a velociraptor is, that anything exists in Nature which instantiates this form. Only if God chooses to endow a piece of matter with this form will any velociraptors exist in Nature.

Finally, I might add that my earlier remarks on the incompleteness of our ideas of non-existent objects apply here, as well. Unicorns have no well-defined essences: our concept of a unicorn, like that of a winged horse or a phoenix, is only skin-deep.

An anti-Fregean argument by Feser

Cat on a fence. Image courtesy of Wikipedia. Feser argues that the question, “What makes it the case that there is anything which falls under the concept of being a cat?” is a meaningful one, and that it can only be answered by positing a real distinction between a cat’s essence and its existence.

In his book, Scholastic Metaphysics (editiones scholasticae, 2014), Feser puts forward an anti-Fregean argument in support of the claim that there is a real distinction between a thing’s essence and its existence:

There is, in any event, ample reason to doubt that the Fregean notion of existence captures everything that needs to be captured by an analysis of existence. Consider that when we are told that “Cats exist” means “There is at least one x such that x is a cat” or that something falls under the concept of being a cat, there is still the question of what makes this the case, of what it is exactly in virtue of which there is something falling under this concept. (2014, p. 253)

Citing the work of philosophers John Knasas and David Braine, Feser suggests that it is precisely in order to answer this question that we need to posit a real distinction between a cat’s essence and its existence: the latter is joined to the former as act to potency.

Let me begin by observing that even if Feser can demonstrate the falsity or inadequacy of the Fregean account of existence, this by no means establishes the truth of the Thomistic account which Feser is defending.

I would also add that I have no wish to defend the Fregean account as an adequate theory of existence. Personally, I have major reservations regarding such an account, as it seems incapable of even expressing what theists mean when they assert that there is a God.

In any case, it strikes me that Feser’s question, “What makes it the case that there is something falling under the concept of ‘being a cat’?” could be properly answered, simply by rephrasing the question as follows: “What causes cats to exist?” This is the sort of question which a scientist or a keen student of nature could answer, and it does not require us to conceive of cats’ essences having existence “poured into” them, like a bottle being filled with a beverage.

What I am proposing, in other words, is that Feser’s question appears puzzling only because of the form in which it is cast: it reifies the concept of “being a cat,” and then looks for a reason why some concepts are instantiated by one or more existent things, while others have nothing out there corresponding to them. But to construe the problem in this way is already to envisage concepts as inhabiting some shadowy, half-real world, waiting to have the fire of existence breathed into them. In short: ask a loaded question, and you’ll get a loaded answer.

Evaluation of Feser’s arguments for a real distinction between essence and existence

I conclude that none of Feser’s three arguments for a real distinction between a thing’s essence and its existence actually work. The first argument points to a form-matter distinction rather than an essence-existence distinction; the second establishes that contingent beings require an external cause, without showing that their natures are distinct from their existence; and the third demonstrates at most that if there are multiple beings whose essences are identical with their existence, then either the existence of these beings is something complex, or these beings resemble one another in a purely analogical fashion.

===================================================================

(f) Lack of logico-mathematical notation: a common flaw in all of Feser’s arguments

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

“The Scream,” by Edvard Munch (1893). National Gallery of Norway. Public domain. Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

My reaction to all of Feser’s arguments for a real distinction between essence and existence can be illustrated by the painting above: they make me want to scream in frustration, because they are not formulated in the precise language of logic and mathematics. Arguments don’t have to be formulated that way, of course: but if you want the logic of your argument to be publicly checkable, then you need to express it in some kind of logico-mathematical notation. Otherwise what you get is two camps of philosophers shouting at one another: “But the conclusion of the argument is obvious! How can you be so blind as not to see it?” – “Doesn’t look at all obvious to us!” How is a layperson to adjudicate between these opposing camps? Clearly, we need an independent yardstick for assessing the validity of philosophers’ arguments. But in the absence of formal notation, we lack such a yardstick.

Now, Feser may protest, as he does in his book (2017, pp. 137-138) that the notation currently employed by most logicians presupposes a Fregean view of existence, which Thomists reject, as it treats existence as a second-order predicate of concepts, rather than as a first-order predicate of individuals. Very well, then: let him put forward a new, Thomistic notation, and use that to validate his argument. And yes, I do realize, of course, that Feser wants his book to reach as wide an audience as possible, and that lay readers may be turned off when they encounter logical notation in a book about the existence of God, but that is what appendices are for. Feser’s book is intended not just for laypeople but for everyone – layperson and scholar alike – and he needs to state his argument rigorously, in order to convince his more sharp-minded critics. (It may interest readers to know that a group of Polish Thomistic philosophers – known as the Cracow Circle – attempted a complete axiomatisation and formalization of Thomism, back in the 1930s. Here, for instance, is their attempted reconstruction of Aquinas’ First Way. So far, I have not been able to find any English translations of their works, online.)

Fortunately, Feser’s remarks on pages 137-138 on the factual statement, “Martians do not exist” (which he construes to mean, “Martians, which are of themselves existentially neutral, do not in fact exist”), provide us with a hint as to what kind of logical notation might suit Feser. In the tradition of Frege and Quine, the existential quantifier symbol (∃) means both “there is” and “exists,” but some logicians use another symbol, E!, to denote actual existence. Thus “Pterodactyls do not exist” (to use one of Feser’s examples) would then be written (∃x)(Px & -E!x), where P means “is a pterodactyl” and – means “not”: in other words, there are (existentially neutral) x’s [objects] which are pterodactyls and which do not actually exist.

===================================================================

(g) Formalizing and re-evaluating Feser’s arguments

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

Feser’s first argument can now be stated as follows: since I can know that (∃x)(Px) [there are pterodactyls] without knowing that (∃x)(Px & -E!x) [there are pterodactyls which really exist], it follows that P is not the same as E! [the predicate, “is-a-pterodactyl” is not the same as the predicate, “really exists.”] Feser’s second argument can then be stated in the following form: (∃x)(Lx & ◇-E!x), where “L” denotes “is a lion” and “◇” denotes “possibly” – in other words, there are some (existentially neutral) x’s [objects] which are lions and which are possibly non-existent, which again highlights the distinction between L (lionhood) and E! (actual existence). Feser’s third argument (insofar as it relates to specific differences between things) can be expressed by pointing out that for any two natural kind predicates F and G (say, “is-a-lion” and “is-a-pterodactyl”), if we were to suppose that F = E! and G = E! then it would follow that F = G, which is obviously false. So in general, we need to draw a distinction between a natural kind predicate and the actual existence operator E! See? That wasn’t so hard, was it?

How convincing are these arguments, when couched in mathematical form? While they are a lot clearer, the assumption underlying them all should be readily apparent: they all treat (real) existence as a first-order predicate of individual objects, and they all treat (real) existence as a univocal predicate, which applies to all objects in the same fashion (which is rather inconsistent of Feser to maintain, given that Thomists hold that existence is a analogical predicate). Feser could perhaps remedy the latter charge of inconsistency by using a different E! predicate for each natural kind – e.g. E!p for pterodactyls, E!l for lions, E!u for unicorns – but then he would have to give up his third argument for a real distinction between essence and existence: for any two natural kind predicates F and G, if we were to suppose that F = E!f and G = E!g then it would no longer follow that F = G, after all, and so the reductio ad absurdum would be avoided. However, Feser’s first and second arguments would still work: for instance, since I can know that (∃x)(Px) without knowing that (∃x)(Px & -E!px), it still follows that P is not the same as E!p.

Now I would readily grant that if real existence were a first-order predicate of the sort described above, then it could not be identified with any natural kind predicate, such as that of being a pterodactyl. But this assumption needs to be argued for. Feser needs to make a strong case, explaining why it is better to regard (real) existence as a first-order predicate of individuals, rather than as a second-order property of concepts (as Frege held) or of propositional functions (as Russell considered it to be). Regarding this point, let us recall the passage quoted above from Professor Michael Nelson’s article in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on Essence and Existence, which remarks that all theories of existence have problems associated with them. At the very least, Feser needs to show that the theory he is propounding faces fewer problems than its rivals, making it a better theory overall. He also needs to formalize his theory of existence, so that it can be critically evaluated.

That brings us to an end of our probing of the “first layer” of Feser’s four-layered Thomistic proof of God’s existence – a layer which turns out to be made of jelly, as we found the arguments supporting it to be inconclusive, and the metaphysical assumptions underlying these arguments to be highly contentious. The only thing going for Feser at this point is that rival theories of existence are not without their own problems. Still, Feser’s own view on existence remains a tenable one, at least, and for all I know, it may turn out to be right. What about the rest of his argument? How does it fare?

===================================================================

3. Feser’s argument that there’s at least one Being whose essence and existence are identical

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

I shall now examine the “second layer” of Feser’s four-tiered Thomistic proof, in which Feser attempts to argue for the existence of a being (or beings) whose essence and existence are identical. In so doing, I shall proceed under the assumption that Feser has demonstrated that there is, in fact, a real distinction between a material thing’s essence and its existence, despite the fact that Feser’s arguments for such a distinction were found to be severely flawed in part 2 above.

In order to demonstrate that there is at least one Being whose essence and existence are identical, Feser first proceeds to argue that anything whose essence and existence are really distinct requires an external cause for its existence. Having shown that, Feser then goes on to argue that this cause must belongs to a hierarchical series in which each member’s action is simultaneous with the effect it brings about. As I pointed out in my previous post, hierarchical causal series require a first member, since the intermediate causes in such a series possess their power in a purely derivative sense, so we are forced to postulate the existence of a First Cause which possesses causal power inherently, and which is distinct from, but simultaneous with, its effect(s). This First Cause must be a being whose essence and existence are identical – otherwise it, too, would require an external cause for its existence.

(a) Why anything whose essence and existence are distinct requires an external cause

In the previous section, I likened ordinary beings to jugs which are filled with liquid – where the jugs represent their essence, and the liquid, their existence. Just as there is nothing about the nature of a jug which guarantees that it will be filled with liquid, so too, there is nothing in the nature (or essence) of an ordinary being which ensures that it will exist. There are, after all, lots of things whose essences are not endowed with actual existence: unicorns, phoenixes and fairies, to name a few. So, what makes those things which actually exist so lucky? What “breathes fire” into them? The answer, argues Feser, can only be: some external cause which imparts existence to them. The cause cannot be an internal one, for as Feser puts it, “A thing can’t impart or add something, or indeed do anything at all for that matter, unless it first exists,” and “a thing whose essence and existence are distinct cannot exist until existence is added or imparted to its essence” (2017, p. 124). So any being whose essence is really distinct from its essence must have an outside cause of its existence:

12. For anything the essence of which is really distinct from its existence, its existence must be imparted to it either by itself or by some cause distinct from it.
13. But if it imparted existence to itself, it would be the cause of itself.
14. Nothing can be the cause of itself.
15. So, it cannot impart existence to itself.
16. So for anything the essence of which is really distinct from its existence, its existence must be imparted to it by some cause distinct from it.

Up to this point, Feser’s argument is rock-solid, assuming that there is a real distinction between a material thing’s essence and its existence. The conclusion in step 16 follows straightforwardly from the Thomistic axiom that “Nothing gives itself what it does not have.” In the next stage, Feser attempts to show that anything whose essence and existence are distinct requires the existence of a concurrent First Cause, in whom they are identical.

===================================================================

(b) Why anything whose essence and existence are distinct requires a concurrent First Cause

How Feser uses a sledgehammer to crack a walnut – and still fails!

Feser uses the example of a dog named Fido to argue for that things whose essence and existence are distinct require a concurrent First Cause (or causes), whose essence is existence itself, to maintain them in existence. Image courtesy of Cheryl Brind and Wikipedia.

In order to argue for a First Cause (or causes) which continually maintains things in existence, Feser employs a seven-step argument which proceeds so painstakingly that it could fairly described as metaphysical overkill, like using a sledgehammer to crack a walnut. Despite its rigor, the hammer still manages to miss the nut, as Feser overlooks a vital point about simultaneity. Fortunately, this mistake is easily remedied. The conclusion of the argument, however, contains an illicit slide, as we’ll see below.

To illustrate his point that that the ordinary things of our experience, whose essence and existence are really distinct, not only require an external cause of their existence, but a concurrent one, Feser uses the example of a dog, named Fido:

Fido’s existence here and now is distinct from his essence and doesn’t follow from its essence. So, here and now there must be some cause which adds or imparts existence to that essence… Let’s call this cause C. Suppose that C, like Fido, is something whose own essence is distinct from its existence. Then what we said about Fido and about the other things of our experience applies no less to C. C too must have a cause here and now which imparts existence to its essence. Let’s call this further cause B. Suppose that B, like Fido and like C, is also something whose essence is distinct from its existence. Then B, here and now, will require a cause of its own, which we might label A. And of course, what was said about C and B will also apply to A, if A is something whose essence is distinct from its existence. (2017, pp. 125-126)

So we have a series of causes, maintaining Fido in existence. But as we saw in the previous post, causal series come in only two varieties: linear (in which each cause possesses causal power in its own right) and hierarchical (in which only the first cause in the series possesses built-in causal power, which it imparts to the other members of the series). As we have seen, causes A, B and C in the series which keeps Fido in existence possess only a derivative causal power, with each cause requiring another cause that imparts existence to its essence here and now, in order for it to act. Such a series requires a First Cause whose power is built-in. And in this First Cause, essence and existence must be identical, or else it would require an external cause, too. We are therefore forced to postulate “something the essence of which is identical to existence, something which just is existence itself” (2017, p. 126).

Feser’s seven-step argument for the existence of a being (or beings) whose essence is Existence itself

Feser argues that the causal series maintaining a thing in existence must be a hierarchical series, rather than a linear one. Image courtesy of shareicon.net.

Feser’s formal, seven-step argument that anything whose essence and existence are really distinct requires a concurrent First Cause, whose essence is Existence itself, can now be set out as follows:

17. Since its essence and existence remain really distinct at every moment at which it exists, including here and now, its existence must be imparted to it by some cause distinct from it at every moment at which it exists, including here and now.
18. So, for each of the things we know from experience, its existence must be imparted to it by some cause distinct from it at every moment at which it exists, including here and now.
19. Either this cause is itself something the essence of which is distinct from its existence, or it is something whose essence and existence are identical, something that just is subsistent existence itself.
20. If this cause is something the essence of which is distinct from its existence, then its own existence too must be imparted to it by some cause distinct from it at every moment at which it exists, including here and now.
21. The causal series this would generate would be a hierarchical one, which cannot regress infinitely but must have a first member.
22. The first member could only be something whose essence and existence are identical, something that just is subsistent existence itself.
23. So, either directly or indirectly, each of the things we know from experience has its existence imparted to it at every moment at which it exists, including here and now, by some cause whose essence and existence are identical, something that just is subsistent existence itself. (2017, pp. 129-130)

What’s wrong with this argument? Two things: first, it assumes the transitivity of simultaneity; second, it equates a being’s having an essence identical to its own existence with a being’s having an essence which is Pure Existence.

Does Feser’s argument hinge on the transitivity of simultaneity?

Two watches. The watch on the left has a mechanical movement that ticks 6 times a second, while the quartz watch on the right moves the seconds hand once a second. Feser’s argument for the existence of a being(s) whose essence and existence are identical assumes the transitivity of simultaneity: that if A is simultaneous with B, and B with C, then A is simultaneous with C. However, this only holds if A, B and C are all at the same location. Image courtesy of Hustvedt and Wikipedia.

In step 18 of his proof, Feser argues that “for each of the things we know from experience, its existence must be imparted to it by some cause distinct from it at every moment at which it exists, including here and now.” In step 23, he concludes that “each of the things we know from experience has its existence imparted to it at every moment at which it exists, including here and now, by some cause whose essence and existence are identical.” But this doesn’t follow. From the fact that C is being maintained in existence here and now by B, which is being maintained here and now by A, it does not follow, as a matter of strict logic, that C is being (indirectly) maintained in existence here and now by A. That would follow only if simultaneity were a transitive relation, such that if C is simultaneous with B, and B is simultaneous with A, then C is simultaneous with A. This assumption would be entirely legitimate, even in a relativistic universe, if each of the causes in the series occupied the same spatial location. Unfortunately, nowhere in his proof does Feser supply us with any reason for thinking that they do. Indeed, it is difficult to envisage how they could occupy the same point in space, if each cause is distinct from and external to its immediate effect. Two physical entities in a chain of causes might meet at a particular point where they come into contact, but three?

Feser could have avoided this difficulty by asserting at the very beginning of his seven-step argument that any being whose essence and existence are distinct possesses causal power only in a derivative sense, which means that it belongs to a hierarchical series, in which it is true by definition that the action of the First Cause is simultaneous with all of its effects, down the chain. When I say “down the chain,” of course, I don’t mean to exclude the alternative possibility, pointed out by Feser (2017, pp. 64-65), that the First Cause may be external to the whole chain and in direct contact with each member, even if it turns out to be infinite in length. (In his Thomistic proof, Feser is agnostic as to whether the First Cause acts “directly or indirectly” – see step 23.)

Feser could also have pointed out that the very notion of a chain of physical causes maintaining Fido in existence makes absolutely no sense, for as Aquinas remarked (Summa Theologica, I, q. 45, art. 5), “it is absurd to suppose that a body can create [i.e. maintain an object in being – VJT], for no body acts except by touching or moving; and thus it requires in its action some pre-existing thing, which can be touched or moved, which is contrary to the very idea of creation.” Indeed, Aquinas goes even further: he contends that since being is the most universal of all effects, “it must be the proper effect of the first and most universal cause”; hence, “to create can be the action of God alone.” In that case, there can be no chain of causes maintaining Fido in existence: he is kept in being by the immediate action of the Being whose essence is Existence itself. Perhaps Feser would say that this is proceeding a little too quickly; however, at the very least, he should have pointed out that nothing in the argument requires the causes in the chain to be physical agents.

Finally, Feser should have been careful to state that a thing’s being maintained in existence here and now by its cause does not imply that the cause exists within time; all it presupposes is that the cause can interface with beings existing within time.

I conclude that while Feser’s seven-step argument assumes the transitivity of simultaneity, it doesn’t hinge on this assumption, and that it can be reformulated in a way which avoids the assumption it makes, that simultaneity is a transitive relation.

Feser’s illicit slide

Left: A cricket bat. Image courtesy of ARv94 and Wikipedia.
Right: A table tennis bat. Image courtesy of PJ, Piko and Wikipedia.
———————————

Are we out of the woods yet? Sadly, not. Unfortunately, Feser’s argument is marred by an illicit slide in the very last step:

23. So, directly or indirectly, each of the things we know from experience has its existence imparted to it at every moment at which it exists, including here and now, by some cause whose essence and existence are identical, something that just is subsistent existence itself. (2017, p. 130)

I am afraid this simply doesn’t follow. It is one thing to argue for a Being whose essence is identical with its own act of existence; quite another to argue for a Being whose essence is Pure Existence, or “subsistent existence itself.” Feser makes the same mistake on page 120, in his informal statement of the Thomistic proof, when he states that “if some thing’s essence and existence are not really distinct, then they are identical; and if they are identical in that thing, then that thing would be something whose essence just is existence itself.” But why couldn’t there be two beings, A and B, such that A is identical with its own existence (call it existence-A), while B is identical with its existence (call it existence-B)?

Feser might object that “existence” would then be predicated of them both in a purely equivocal sense (as when we use the term “bat” to refer to both a flying mammal and a stick we use to play baseball with), but this need not be the case: A and B could still resemble one another analogically, insofar as each entity has the same relation to its own act of existence (namely, identity), and each is a cause of other entities, whose essence and existence are distinct. The analogical similarity between existence-A and existence-B would be like that between a cricket bat and a table tennis bat: despite their strikingly different appearance, each of them is used to hit a ball.

As we’ll see below in part 7, there are good reasons for thinking that the very notion of “Pure Existence” is utterly nonsensical; but on the other hand, it makes perfect sense to suppose that a being might be identical with its own act of existence.

To sum up: The “second layer” of Feser’s argument remains standing, after some modifications, but it doesn’t establish what he wants it to establish – namely, the existence of some Being (or beings) which is Existence itself. Rather, what it establishes is the existence of one or more beings, each of which is identical to its own act of existence. It still remains to be seen if Feser can demonstrate that there is only one such being.

===================================================================

4. Feser’s argument for the uniqueness and necessity of the Being whose essence is its own existence

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

We have now arrived at the “third layer” of Feser’s four-tiered Thomistic proof, in which Feser argues that there is only One Being whose essence and existence are identical, that this Being is the Cause of the existence of all other beings, and that this Being is a Necessary Being.

As we saw in section 3 above, Feser believes he has now established the following conclusion:

23. So, either directly or indirectly, each of the things we know from experience has its existence imparted to it at every moment at which it exists, including here and now, by some cause whose essence and existence are identical, something that just is subsistent existence itself.

I have critiqued Feser’s arguments for this conclusion above, but henceforth, I shall take it as a given that there is at least one Being whose essence and existence are identical, and which is Pure Existence itself.

(a) Uniqueness of the Being whose essence is its own existence

Image courtesy of rixwiki.org.

But how do we know that there is only one such Being? Feser arrives at this conclusion by appealing to some earlier premises in his argument, where he argued that there is at most one Being whose essence is identical to its own existence:

6. If there could in principle be more than one thing the essence of which is identical to its existence, then two or more such things would be distinguishable in the way that species of the same genus are distinguished, or members of the same species are distinguished, or in some other way.
7. But they cannot be distinguished in any of these ways.
8. So, there could not in principle be more than one thing the essence of which is identical to its existence.

We previously criticized this argument in section 2(e) above, when evaluating Feser’s third argument for a real distinction between an ordinary thing’s essence and its existence. As we saw, the argument equivocates between (i) a thing’s essence being identical to its own act of existence and (ii) a thing’s essence being identical to Pure Existence itself, in order to justify its conclusion that there is at most one Being whose essence and existence are identical. Combining this with premise 23 above, which states that there is at least one such Being, we may conclude that there is exactly one Being whose essence is identical to its own existence:

24. Since there cannot in principle be more than one being the essence of which is identical to its existence, this cause which is subsistent existence itself is unique. (2017, p. 130)

The above conclusion also equivocates between “a being whose essence is identical to its own existence” and “a being whose essence is subsistent existence itself.” The two concepts are not equivalent, and Feser has supplied us with no convincing reason why there could not be multiple beings, each of which is identical with its own act of existence.

===================================================================

(b) Why the Being whose essence is its own existence is also the Ultimate Cause of everything else

Image courtesy of theosophical.files.wordpress.com.

Feser next endeavors to how that the unique Being whose essence is its own existence is also the cause of everything other than itself, by appealing once again to premise 23, which states that anything whose essence and existence are really distinct has its existence imparted to it, directly or indirectly, by some external cause, whose essence and existence are identical. Since (as Feser has argued above) there is only one such Cause, it follows that this Being must be the Ultimate Cause of everything else:

25. Since it is unique, anything other than it which exists must be something the essence of which is distinct from its existence.
26. Anything the essence of which is distinct from its existence will, either directly or indirectly, have its existence imparted to it by a cause which is subsistent existence itself.
27. So, this unique cause which is subsistent existence itself is the cause of everything other than itself. (2017, p. 130)

This part of Feser’s proof, at least, is logically valid.

===================================================================

(c) Why the Being whose essence is its own existence is also a Necessary Being

Finally, Feser invokes premises 4 and 5 of his argument, to argue that this Ultimate Cause, whose essence and existence are identical, must be a necessary Being:

4. If it [the distinction between essence and existence] were not a real distinction, then the things we know from experience would exist in a necessary way rather than a merely contingent way.
5. But in fact they exist in a merely contingent way, and not in a necessary way. (2017, pp. 128-129)

Feser concludes:

28. Since whatever lacks a real distinction between its essence and its existence would exist in a necessary rather than contingent way, this unique cause which is subsistent existence itself exists in a necessary way. (2017, p. 130)

At first glance, this may appear to be a non sequitur, as Feser does not explain why a Being which lacks a real distinction between its essence and its existence would have to be a necessary Being, in his formal statement of the Thomistic proof. However, two pages earlier, in his informal statement of the argument, Feser provides a brief explanation: “For since its very essence would just be existence itself, it would not and could not fail to exist” (2017, p. 127). And on page 119, Feser adds that such a Being “would exist by its very nature, and would therefore not be contingent at all but necessary – that is to say, it would be something that could not possibly not exist, not even in principle.” In other words, since Feser thinks it is obvious that a Being whose essence is identical with its own existence would have to be Pure Existence itself, he can argue that this Being’s nature is simply to exist. Since this Being is not composed of essence plus existence, but is simply Existence itself, it requires nothing to hold it together, and therefore cannot fail to exist.

Hypothetical or absolute necessity?

However, Feser’s assertion that a Being whose essence is Existence itself “could not fail to exist” is ambiguous: it might mean that the non-existence of such a Being is impossible (making its existence absolutely necessary), or it might mean that the going out of existence of such a Being is impossible, if it exists, but that the existence of this Being is an unexplained “brute fact” (making it only hypothetically necessary). Now, it seems quite obvious that a being which is Existence itself would require nothing but itself for its continued existence, if it exists. However, it is not clear why such a Being would have to exist in the first place, as its non-existence would entail no contradiction. (“There is no being whose essence is Existence itself” is a logically consistent utterance, on the face of it.) Even if we have good independent grounds – namely, the existence of composite, contingent beings – for concluding that there is indeed a Being whose essence is Existence itself, we can still ask: what guarantees that such a Being will exist, in the first place? It therefore appears to me that Feser has merely shown that such a Being is hypothetically necessary, rather than absolutely necessary.

Feser’s illicit assumption

Finally, Feser’s argument once again relies upon the assumption that the Being whose essence is identical to its own existence is also a Being whose essence is Pure Existence. Since this assumption has not been justified, and since (even if it can be justified) Feser has only established that such a Being is hypothetically necessary, I am forced to conclude that Feser’s arguments for the uniqueness and necessity of a being whose essence is identical to its existence are less than cogent.

In short: the “third layer” of Feser’s Thomistic proof needs some additional fortification, in order to prevent its collapse.

===================================================================

5. Feser’s argument for the pure actuality of the Being whose essence is its own existence

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

An image of the Sun, a metaphor for God’s Pure Actuality. Image courtesy of Arun Kulshreshtha and Wikipedia.

Finally, we come to the “fourth layer” of Feser’s four-tiered Thomistic proof, in which Feser argues that the unique Necessary Being which is Pure Existence and which keeps everything else in existence must be fully actual and therefore “immutable, eternal, immaterial, incorporeal, perfect, omnipotent, fully good, intelligent, and omniscient,” which warrants it being called “God.”

(a) From Pure Being to Pure Actuality

Feser argues that the Being whose essence is Pure Existence must be a purely actual being, as follows:

29. Whatever is subsistent existence itself need not and could not have had a cause of its own.
30. So, this unique cause which is subsistent existence itself is uncaused.
31. If that which is subsistent existence itself had some potentiality for existence which needed to be actualized, then existence would have to be imparted to it by some cause.
32. So, that which is subsistent existence itself has no potential for existence which needs actualization, but rather exists in a purely actual way. (2017, p. 130)

As I pointed out in Part 4 of my previous post, all that Feser has actually shown here is that a Being which is Pure Existence contains no potentialities within its being. This in no way precludes the possibility that such a Being may be capable of realizing potentialities when it acts. Having no potential for existence is not the same as being fully actual in every respect.

===================================================================

(b) From Pure Actuality to Divinity

Having argued that a Being which is Pure Existence must be purely actual, Feser then attempts to argue that this Being deserves to be called “God,” by invoking a conclusion which he arrived at in chapter one of his book (the Aristotelian proof), whose flawed logic I exposed in my previous post:

33. Whatever is purely actual must be immutable, eternal, immaterial, incorporeal, perfect, omnipotent, fully good, intelligent, and omniscient. (2017, p. 131)

And as I pointed out in my second-last post, even if we assume that there is a purely actual Being, Feser has not shown that this Being is perfect, omnipotent, fully good, or omniscient. All he has shown is the following:

(i) that a purely actual Being would contain no imperfections (which is quite different from saying that it is perfect – after all, we don’t normally call electrons “perfect” because they are free from flaws);

(ii) that everything else depends on this Being (but not that it is capable of doing absolutely anything, or even that it is capable of doing anything which is consistent with its nature);

(iii) that it is a perfect specimen of its kind, insofar as it has no abnormalities (but not that it contains all possible perfections, let alone that it is it is benevolently disposed towards us, or cares about us individually); and

(iv) that it has a Mind which contains all universals (if Feser’s arguments in chapter three stand up to scrutiny), but not that it actually knows any true propositions, let alone that it knows all true propositions.

Since Feser needs to establish that a Being which is Pure Existence possesses all of these attributes, in order to qualify as worthy of being called “God,” as Feser declares Him to be in steps 35 and 36 of his argument, I am forced to conclude that the “fourth layer” of Feser’s Thomistic proof of the existence of God fails to live up to its promises.

===================================================================

6. A Critical Evaluation of Feser’s Fourth, Thomistic Proof

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

A four-layered wedding cake. Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

I began my discussion of Feser’s Thomistic proof by likening it to a four-tiered wedding cake. After my critical analysis, how do the layers stack up?

As we have seen, the argument rests on shaky metaphysical foundations. The arguments Feser put forward for a real distinction between essence and existence in ordinary entities turned out to be inconclusive at best, even when I attempted to formalize them (something which Feser should have done, himself), as they all rely on the questionable assumption that actual existence is a first-order predicate of individual objects. Nevertheless, this assumption may (for all I know) turn out to be correct. So the bottom layer of Feser’s cake still stands, but it’s looking rather unstable.

The second layer of the argument, in which Feser attempts to argue for the existence of an Ultimate Cause (or causes) whose essence and existence are identical, was very heavily buttressed by Feser, in a way which I likened to using a sledgehammer to crack a walnut. As we saw, Feser’s carefully constructed argument doesn’t quite work, but it is easily remediable.

The third layer of the argument, where Feser attempts to establish the uniqueness and necessity of the Being whose essence is its own existence, doesn’t stack up: it relies on fallacious claims (made earlier in Feser’s argument) that if the essence and existence of ordinary beings were identical, this would entail, counterfactually, that they were all necessary and that they were all the same being.

The fourth layer, or top tier, of Feser’s argument, in which he argues that this One, Necessary Being whose essence is its own existence must be purely actual and hence possess all the attributes which warrant our calling it God, fares no better: it relies on slipshod metaphysical reasoning which hangs heavily on Feser’s Aristotelian proof of God’s existence (discussed here) and which I critiqued in an earlier post.

So, at the end, all we can say is that only the bottom two layers of Feser’s cake are still standing. And as we have seen, the first layer of the cake turned out to be made of jelly: arguments for a real distinction between the essence and existence of ordinary things proved to be highly questionable. On top of that, we saw that the second layer of Feser’s four-tiered Thomistic proof was marred by an illicit slide: all it establishes is the existence of one or more beings, each of which is identical to its own act of existence. Such an argument does not take us anywhere near a Being which we would call God.

===================================================================

7. Why I think Aquinas’ and Feser’s claim that God’s essence is Pure Existence implies atheism

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

Wrong Way sign, State of Delaware. Public domain image courtesy of Wikipedia.

In any case, I think Aquinas’ and Feser’s claim that God’s essence is Pure Existence has a disastrous implication: it renders the very notion of God nonsensical. Hence it cannot be true.

How should we logically express the statement, “God exists”?

To see why, let’s consider the statement, “God exists.” How are we to construe this statement? We might begin by saying, (∃x)(Dx & E!x), where D denotes the predicate “is-divine.” But that formulation fails to express Aquinas’ insight that God’s essence simply is Pure Existence, and it also fails to express Feser’s point (2017, pp. 194-195) that God is necessarily unique, as a predicate D might be instantiated by many individuals.

Or we might say: □(∃x)(Dx & E!x & (y)(Dy ⊃ y=x)), where the modal operator “□” means “necessarily.” In other words, it is a necessary truth that one and only one divine being actually exists. However, this formulation also fails to express Aquinas’ insight that God’s essence is Pure Existence, and it suffers from the additional defect of making necessity either something extrinsic to the concept of divinity (D), as an add-on feature, or (if we make the above statement a definition of D) it fails to elucidate what the concept of divinity means: all we are told is that necessarily, there is one and only one actually existing Being which possesses it. But what is it?

So we might say: (∃x)(E!x & (F)(-Fx v F=E!)), which means that there is some being (or object) such that existence is the only predicate that can be ascribed to it (assuming that we restrict our domain of predicates to those denoting intrinsic properties, rather than Cambridge properties, which describe things in purely relative terms). And we could then show that there can be only one such such being, by arguing that if there were two, their intrinsic properties would be indistinguishable, and that any two beings must always differ in some intrinsic property. (Note that I’m using the term “property” broadly here, in its modern sense.) One could still ask, however, why it has to be the case that there is any being such that existence is the only intrinsic “property” that can be ascribed to it. Why couldn’t there be none? What makes this being’s existence necessary?

Even leaving aside this difficulty relating to necessity, this revised formula still won’t do, as it treats God as an individual x, which has the sole property of existing, which runs counter to Aquinas’ insistence that God simply is Pure Existence.

So we might try to use a notation which eliminates the requirement that predicates have to modify a bound variable like x, which stands for some individual, and allow predicates to modify predicates, as well. We might then express “God exists” like this: (E!E! & (F)(-FE!vF=E!)). In other words, existence exists, and it has no other properties.

And now we can see what’s wrong with the claim that God’s essence is Pure Existence: what it boils down to is the incoherent assertion that Existence exists. There are three powerful reasons for believing that this statement makes absolutely no sense.

===================================================================

Why the concept of Pure Existence makes no sense

(a) The notion of “existence” is utterly indefinite

A male lion lying down in Namibia. The statement that at least one lion exists is informative; the statement that at least one being exists is not. Image courtesy of Kevin Pluck and Wikipedia.

First, the bare notion of “existence” is completely uninformative. Consider the sentence, “At least one lion exists.” That tells us something: there are one or more individuals which belong to that species of big cats whose males typically possess manes. Now compare this with the sentence: “At least one being exists.” What does this sentence tell us? Absolutely nothing. To call something a being is to say nothing at all about it.

Now Feser would vigorously contest the foregoing assertion of mine: as a Thomist, he views existence (or being) as a transcendental, which is free from any inherent limitations of its own, and which contains no internal divisions. This leads him to infer that anything which is Pure Existence would (if it existed) have to be simple and infinite. On this view, to say that at least one being exists would mean: Pure Existence exists, and possibly one or more complex, finite individuals, whose essences are distinct from their acts of existence.

But it would be a profound mistake, in my opinion, to draw any positive conclusions about something which is Pure Existence from the mere fact that the general concept of “existence” is free from any limitations or internal complexity. Rather, what we should say is that “existence per se” is neither finite nor infinite, and neither simple nor complex, but indefinite: it has no features of its own. It is a failing of Feser’s latest book that he makes no attempt to tease out these distinctions. Nor does he attempt to defend the Thomist concept of God’s infinity against the Scotist objection that a being’s simplicity does not entail its infinity, and that infinity must be construed as something positive, rather than as the mere absence of limitations.

===================================================================

(b) To ascribe activities to Pure Existence is to reify an abstraction

There is a second reason why the statement, “Existence exists,” makes absolutely no sense, which we can appreciate by considering it with the following parallel statements, which are all in the same vein:

Walking walks.
Exercising exercises.
Seeing sees.
Thinking thinks.
Loving loves.
Action acts.

Everyone would agree that the foregoing statements make no sense. The philosophical question is: why, exactly?

What’s wrong with all these statements, I would suggest, is that they reify an abstraction by ascribing an action to it, thereby treating it as both abstract and concrete at once, which makes no sense. And, I would argue, the claim that Existence exists commits exactly the same fallacy. “Existence” is an abstraction; “exists” describes a concrete action (a particular entity’s act of existing). The statement “Existence exists,” I would submit, is every bit as nonsensical as the statements, “Lionhood hunts in packs,” “Happiness is happy,” or “Goodness does good deeds.”

A 14th century fresco of St. Gregory of Nyssa (335-395 A.D.), a fourth-century bishop who was arguably the first theologian to equate God with Pure Existence – a fatal wrong turn, in my view. Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

Readers may be wondering how Christians became accustomed to accepting such a nonsensical way of talking about God. As far as I can tell, this way of speaking about God seems to have arisen in the late fourth century. Its first exponent in the East was St. Gregory of Nyssa (335-394 A.D.), and in the West, St. Augustine (354-430 A.D.), who referred to God in his writings as Being itself, i.e., Ipsum Esse or Idipsum Esse (De immort. an. 7, 12; De lib. arb. 3, 20-21; De mor. Eccl. 1, 14, 24, in: Emile Zum Brunn, St. Augustine: Being and nothingness (New York, New York: Paragon, 1988), p. 101). Thereafter, it seems to have become common among both the Eastern and Western Church Fathers (notably Aquinas) to speak of God in this way, although no ecumenical Council has ever defined that God is Being itself.

In order to appreciate the sheer absurdity of identifying God with Pure Existence, I will try substituting “Existence” into some statements which religious believers ordinarily make about God.

Existence is three persons.
Existence became a man.
Existence created the world.
Existence loves you.
Existence talked to Moses.
Existence wants you to go to church on Sundays.

Do any of these sentences make sense? I would respectfully submit that they do not, and that what is wrong with them is that they all ascribe concrete attributes or concrete actions to an abstraction (Pure Existence). If God is concrete, as an agent must be, then He cannot be Pure Existence, or Actuality, or Intelligence, or Love. And if God is not concrete, then He is not an agent, and hence, not God.

===================================================================

(c) Characterizing God as an activity generates an infinite regress

A final reason for rejecting any attempt to characterize God in purely dynamic terms (e.g. as Pure Act, Pure Existence or Pure Understanding) is that the attempt to do so generates an infinite regress.

Scholastics construe existence along the lines of an activity – thus their favorite translation of the Latin verb esse is: “act of existing.” So if God is Pure Existence, then God Himself is an activity. But what kind of activity? The only two activities which can be appropriately ascribed to God are thinking (or understanding) and willing (or choosing), since (a) these activities alone do not involve any kind of limitation, and (b) any being which couldn’t perform these activities would be finite, and hence contingent. (Some readers might be wondering why I didn’t list love, but in Aristotelian philosophy, to love is simply to will someone’s good, so the fact that God loves Himself follows from the fact that He understands Himself and wills His own good.)

Now suppose we try to identify God with the activities of thinking and/or willing (or if you prefer, loving). The next question which arises is: what is the object of these activities? God understands and loves Himself, so we would have to say that Understanding understands understanding, which in turn has to understand … understanding, and so on, ad infinitum. The same goes for love: if God is love, and He loves Himself, then Loves loves love, which in turn loves love, and so on, ad infinitum.

The problem, then, with any attempt to characterize God as an activity is that it generates an infinite regress, leading to metaphysical absurdity.

===================================================================

8. A new way of thinking about God?

RETURN TO MAIN MENU

Let’s take stock of where we are now. As we’ve seen, the attempt to characterize God as Pure Existence, or Actuality, or Intelligence, or Love, makes it impossible for us to ascribe concrete properties to Him, as well as generating an infinite regress. How can we remedy these difficulties? What we need to do, I would suggest, is reject wholesale the attempt to turn God into a verb (or action), because it leads to absurdities. Rather, we need to start with God as a noun: God is not Pure Existence, but a unique Existent; He is not Pure Actuality, but Self-Actualizing Agent; He is not Pure Intelligence, but the Master Intellect; He is not Pure Love, but the Supreme Lover, from Whom all good things come, and to Whom we owe our very existence.

But characterizing God as nothing but a noun tells us absolutely nothing about Him. If God is a big “Something-I-know-not-what” that causes the world to exist, then what can we say about God? We have not yet proved that God is a personal being. But if He were, then we would have to construe God as the Ultimate Agent. The activities of thinking and choosing are an integral part of being an agent. But under the model I am proposing, the object of these activities is typically God Himself, as an Agent. Thus to say that God understands and loves Himself is to say that an Agent understands and loves an Agent. There is no circularity here. Moreover, an agent, unlike a reified action, is also concrete.

I remarked above that what theists should be arguing is that the identity (or essence, or “what-ness”) of contingent beings can only be defined in terms of their relation to their necessary Ultimate Cause. An atheist or pantheist might well concede this point, while disagreeing with theists as to the nature of the Ultimate Cause of the things we encounter in our everyday experience. As I see it, what distinguishes the theistic approach is its insistence that in the end, the most fundamental concept we can possibly have is not a bare spatio-temporal concept (be it that of a wave, a field or a string), but that of a Personal Agent, and that the non-conscious, law-governed agency that we ascribe to material objects can only be understood by starting with the notion of personal agency and then stripping away some of its key characteristics, such as foresight of its goal. Things, in other words, are pale reflections of persons, and laws of Nature are simply mathematical descriptions of things’ built-in goals. But the notion of a thing’s having a goal of any sort makes no sense, unless we view the world as the work of a Universal Agent.

Such is the proposal that a theistic philosopher might make; but it remains to be demonstrated that the claim, “God exists” can be cast into any satisfactory logical notation. And of course, a Kantian would object to the line of reasoning employed in the foregoing paragraph: even if our concepts should prove to be person-centric, that does not prove anything that the external world is the work of a personal Agent. I shall attempt to address these concerns in my next post, in which I shall discuss Feser’s Rationalist and Augustinian proofs of God’s existence. My next post will also be more irenic in tone than the present one.

Here is a list of my posts so far, on Feser’s Five Proofs of the Existence of God (Ignatius Press, 2017):

18 really dumb (and not-so-dumb) objections to arguments for the existence of God

Feser’s predestinationism and his bizarre claim that God’s knowledge is non-propositional

Has Feser proved that God is almighty, all-knowing, good, capable of free choice and loving?

Flawed logic and bad mereology: why Feser’s first two proofs fail

So, what do readers think? Would anyone care to defend Feser’s Thomistic proof of the existence of God? Over to you.

73 thoughts on “Feser’s fourth proof and the mystery of existence

  1. Vjt: Did you really write all that ? How long did it take ?

    What a godawful waste of time.

  2. graham2: What a godawful waste of time.

    I agree with that.

    For most of the people who post here, the kind of philosophical argument that Feser uses is, self-evidently, no good.

  3. vjtorley:

    Feser highlights the distinction between the an object’s essence and its existence by pointing out (in a passage which I’ll discuss below) that “you can know a thing’s essence without knowing whether or not it exists” (2017, p. 118). The phrase “whether or not it exists” would appear to suggest that a thing’s existence is a Boolean data type, with only two possible values: true or false.

    Alternatively, the phrase, “the fact that it is,” might suggest that a thing’s existence is simply the proposition that it exists. Indeed, Feser’s discussion of human beings in an example he provides on page 117 of his book lends support to this interpretation: he points out that you can know “the nature or essence of a human being” without knowing “that there really are human beings,” which seems to imply that a human being’s existence (as opposed to its essence” is simply the proposition that human beings exist.

    But this clearly will not do. For Feser wants to argue that there is one Being – God – in Whom essence and existence are identical. And it is absolutely impossible for a being’s essence to be identical with either a Boolean (true-false) data type or a proposition, no matter what kind of being it is.

    Vincent,

    I’m no fan of Feser or his arguments, but I do think you’re overlooking an interpretation of his definition that avoids the problem you describe.

    Consider a sentence like

    We succeeded due to the fact that we worked so hard.

    Clearly, the author of that sentence is not attributing the success to a boolean variable or a proposition. They’re attributing it to the hard work.

    It’s the actuality of the hard work that is being represented by the phrase “the fact that we worked so hard”.

  4. Vincent in the OP:

    Today, I’m going to argue that this notion of God is utterly nonsensical.

    On Tuesdays and Thursdays I sometimes think it is a reasonable supposition that some creative force was involved in the formation (there’s probably a better word) of the universe we live in.

    But how to get from that creator to the God with the attributes that, for instance, Feser endows him with? From step one two step two involves no more than human imagination. I find Feser’s misogyny pretty objectionable. His justification for capital punishment is repugnant, too. Luckily, his influence is minimal.

    ETA clarity

  5. Left a comment on his blog. ~ “awaiting moderation” ~ So far (24 hrs) no sign of it appearing.

    (I just asked if there were any female commenters.)

  6. Alan Fox: But how to get from that creator to the God with the attributes that, for instance, Feser endows him with?

    The incarnation

    peace

  7. Alan Fox: On Tuesdays and Thursdays I sometimes think it is a reasonable supposition that some creative force was involved in the formation (there’s probably a better word) of the universe we live in.

    More-or-less the same here, except it is Wednesdays and Fridays.

    The problem with all of these evidence-free arguments for god is that, at best, they are arguments for the deist’s idea of god or maybe the pantheist’s idea of god. But, after presenting the argument, there is usually a huge leap to the assumption that they have made a case for the Christian god.

  8. Alan Fox: On Tuesdays and Thursdays I sometimes think it is a reasonable supposition that some creative force was involved in the formation (there’s probably a better word) of the universe we live in.

    I like Stuart Kauffman’s speculation that there are laws of physics in open thermodynamic systems such that systems tend towards greater complexity over time, which we experience as beauty. There’s probably a version of pantheism or religious naturalism I’d be perfectly happy with.

  9. Neil Rickert: The problem with all of these evidence-free arguments for god is that, at best, they are arguments for the deist’s idea of god or maybe the pantheist’s idea of god.

    I agree. If it were not for the incarnation I am sure I would be a Pantheist/Deist of some sort. I honestly think this is the natural default position for humanity and I deeply respect it.

    Christianity is I think unique in that it holds that the transcendent creator deity “unmoved mover” behind the universe somehow became a lower class carpenter in 1st century Palestine.

    And the Word became flesh and all that.

    That such a thing is possible is relatively easy to grant. If you can swing a Big Bang you could do this.

    The hard part for me to understand is why he would possibly do such a thing.

    Once you grasp the reason you are indeed forever and irreparably changed.

    He did it because he loves me. Not some abstract universal mankind kind of “me” but ME personally!!!!!!!!!!!

    A goof-up misfit who is not a particularly good person and is of no particular consequence whatsoever in the apparent overall scheme of things

    That thought is simply amazing.

    There is simply no way to mentally convince someone that the awesome pantheistic/deist entity the philosophers go on about loves them individually but if the message is for you some where deep down you know.

    peace

  10. Kantian Naturalist: There’s probably a version of pantheism or religious naturalism I’d be perfectly happy with.

    I think instead of looking for what makes us happy we should look for what is true.

    If Christianity is correct what is True is the very thing that will make us ultimately happy.

    Not to be all Zen on you

    but it’s possible that seeking the things that we believe would make us happy is the very reason we end up ultimately unhappy.

    peace

  11. Alan Fox: Incarnation? Which one? How do we decide between the versions on offer?

    There is only one on offer.

    A lower case anthropomorphic god like Zeus or Odin or Brahma temporarily putting on a meat costume is not remotely what I mean when I speak of incarnation.

    By incarnation I mean the one thing that stretches logic to it’s very limit.

    The Unmoved Mover, the Great I AM, thought thinking itself, becomes a helpless rejected murdered Jew not temporarily or metaphorically but actually ………..for me.

    peace

  12. fifthmonarchyman: There is simply no way to mentally convince someone that the awesome pantheistic/deist entity the philosophers go on about loves them individually but if the message is for you some where deep down you know.

    You have underestimated human credulity.

  13. Neil Rickert: You have underestimated human credulity.

    I don’t think so

    quote:

    For the word of the cross is folly to those who are perishing, but to us who are being saved it is the power of God. For it is written, “I will destroy the wisdom of the wise, and the discernment of the discerning I will thwart.” Where is the one who is wise? Where is the scribe? Where is the debater of this age? Has not God made foolish the wisdom of the world? For since, in the wisdom of God, the world did not know God through wisdom, it pleased God through the folly of what we preach to save those who believe. For Jews demand signs and Greeks seek wisdom, but we preach Christ crucified, a stumbling block to Jews and folly to Gentiles, but to those who are called, both Jews and Greeks, Christ the power of God and the wisdom of God.
    (1Co 1:18-24)

    end quote:

    That is it in a nutshell.

    There is no way to know God by philosophical “wisdom” or evidential “signs”.

    The only way is to be called.

    peace

  14. I think instead of looking for what makes us happy we should look for what is true.

    …says fifth, while doing exactly the opposite.

    There is simply no way to mentally convince someone that the awesome pantheistic/deist entity the philosophers go on about loves them individually but if the message is for you some where deep down you know.

    In other words, gullible people can believe things that no rational person would ever believe. Especially if they want to believe those things.

    Look at Scientologists. And breatharians. And Christians.

  15. Alan:

    But how to get from that creator to the God with the attributes that, for instance, Feser endows him with?

    fifth:

    The incarnation

    Fifth is as bad at theology as he is at design detection.

    If God’s attributes were contingent on the Incarnation, then they’d be… contingent.

  16. fifth:

    He did it because he loves me. Not some abstract universal mankind kind of “me” but ME personally!!!!!!!!!!!

    Wow. He did all that for YOU personally!!!!!!!!!!!

    Funny how Jesus can’t be bothered to help you out when you’re having your ass handed to you, while trying to defend Christianity here at TSZ. It’s as if he’s been dead for 2000 years, or something.

    You got suckered, fifth.

  17. From Vjt:

    What we need to do, I would suggest, is reject wholesale the attempt to turn God into a verb (or action), because it leads to absurdities. Rather, we need to start with God as a noun …

    Um, after 2000 years, this is as far as you have got ?
    All the countless man years devoted to theology, and this is what you have to show for it ?

  18. fifthmonarchyman: The Unmoved Mover, the Great I AM, thought thinking itself, becomes a helpless rejected murdered Jew not temporarily or metaphorically but actually ………..for me.

    Welcome to the club.

  19. newton: Welcome to the club.

    For God, who said, “Let light shine out of darkness,” has shone in our hearts to give the light of the knowledge of the glory of God in the face of Jesus Christ. But we have this treasure in jars of clay, to show that the surpassing power belongs to God and not to us.
    (2Co 4:6-7)

    😉

    and

    saying, “Would that you, even you, had known on this day the things that make for peace! But now they are hidden from your eyes.
    (Luk 19:42)

    peace

  20. fifthmonarchyman: Don’t you think that is true about mathematics as well?

    Actually — no, I don’t think think that.

    Mathematics is an aggregation of methods. Yes, it also includes descriptions of those methods. But it is not just descriptions.

    Creative fiction, on the other hand, is just descriptions.

  21. graham2,

    Vjt: Did you really write all that? How long did it take?

    About a month. And no, I don’t consider it a waste of time. If you look around the Internet, you’ll see good, bad and indifferent responses to the standard arguments for (and against) God’s existence, with most responses falling into the last two categories. I thought Professor Feser’s book was of sufficient quality as to warrant a serious response, but I wasn’t satisfied with any of the responses I encountered online, which struck me as being either too superficial or too ad hominem. So I decided to write what will, I hope, be recognized as the most in-depth treatment of Feser’s latest book, online.

    Hi keiths,

    It’s the actuality of the hard work that is being represented by the phrase “the fact that we worked so hard”.

    OK. Then what does the phrase “the fact that it is” represent?

    In any case, as I pointed out later, Feser himself says that existence is a first-order predicate.

    Hi Alan Fox,

    Left a comment on his blog. ~ “awaiting moderation” ~ So far (24 hrs) no sign of it appearing.

    (I just asked if there were any female commenters.)

    That doesn’t surprise me. Feser used to let just about any comment through, but in recent months, he has become less tolerant of comments which he would regard as off-topic.

    Hi fifthmonarchyman,

    The Unmoved Mover, the Great I AM, thought thinking itself, becomes a helpless rejected murdered Jew not temporarily or metaphorically but actually ………..for me.

    I agree with you on the Incarnation, and especially on the “for me” bit, but “thought thinking itself” strikes me as a nonsensical description of God, for reasons outlined in part 7 of my OP.

  22. vjtorley: If you look around the Internet, you’ll see good, bad and indifferent responses to the standard arguments for (and against) God’s existence, with most responses falling into the last two categories. I thought Professor Feser’s book was of sufficient quality as to warrant a serious response, but I wasn’t satisfied with any of the responses I encountered online, which struck me as being either too superficial or too ad hominem. So I decided to write what will, I hope, be recognized as the most in-depth treatment of Feser’s latest book, online.

    Let’s see how it goes: I predict that nobody outside of this combox takes note of your article. Nobody in the whole wide internet. Richard Carrier’s piece(s) had a bit more effect.

    This is not only your fault. Proofs of God are passé and not too many people noticed Feser even published the book. Anyway, I bought it and read it. And I can say once again that Torley’s criticism hardly makes any sense, unless we attribute it to lingering personal gripe or envy.

  23. Neil Rickert: Actually — no, I don’t think think that.

    Mathematics is an aggregation of methods.

    So you are a realist when it comes to mathematics?

    peace

  24. fifthmonarchyman: So you are a realist when it comes to mathematics?

    It depends on what that means.

    I’m a fictionalist about mathematical objects. I agree that mathematics itself exists.

    My fictionalism about mathematical objects is actually related to my view that mathematics is an aggregation of methods. The fictional objects are what we use to exercise those methods in our theorizing. But we are able to use those methods with real objects, where appropriate.

  25. vjtorley: “thought thinking itself” strikes me as a nonsensical description of God, for reasons outlined in part 7 of my OP.

    I think you are referring to this statement of yours

    quote:

    I would suggest, is that they reify an abstraction by ascribing an action to it, thereby treating it as both abstract and concrete at once, which makes no sense.

    end quote:

    I would suggest that the expression “thought thinking itself” is not treating the subject as both abstract and concrete “at once” it’s moving from one subject and object to another sequentially.

    Think of Edward’s essay on the Trinity where the love that the Father and Son share for each other is itself a person that loves both the Father and the Son in turn.

    “Lover loving the beloved”, “beloved loving the lover” “love flowing toward both the lover and the beloved”.

    Phrases like this can be seen as holograms of sorts where each word is in turn a subject and a predicate and an object depending on the perspective you are taking. The full meaning is seen when you assume multiple valid perspectives.

    It’s all very Trinitarian and deep but I would not say nonsensical.

    peace

  26. Neil Rickert: I’m a fictionalist about mathematical objects. I agree that mathematics itself exists.

    You are a I’m a fictionalist about theological objects. while agreeing that theology itself exists. correct? 😉

    peace

  27. fifthmonarchyman: You are a I’m a fictionalist about theological objects. while agreeing that theology itself exists. correct?

    I wouldn’t put it quite that way. If by “theological objects” you mean gods (at least), then I don’t actually have a position about whether there are any.

    Theology itself is still creative fiction. Even if there are gods, why theologists say about them is made up stories.

  28. fifthmonarchyman: For God, who said, “Let light shine out of darkness,” has shone in our hearts to give the light of the knowledge of the glory of God in the face of Jesus Christ. But we have this treasure in jars of clay, to show that the surpassing power belongs to God and not to us.
    (2Co 4:6-7)

    Sounds like evidentiary proof God exists, thought that was not a thing along with logic.

  29. newton: Sounds like evidentiary proof God exists, thought that was not a thing along with logic.

    It’s not a evidentiary proof that God exists. It’s evidentiary proof that we don’t deserve any credit for knowing God exists.

    peace

  30. Neil Rickert: Even if there are gods, why theologists say about them is made up stories.

    I would agree on that point.

    The only thing that is true about God is the stuff he reveals about himself.

    peace

  31. Erik: Let’s see how it goes: I predict that nobody outside of this combox takes note of your article. Nobody in the whole wide internet. Richard Carrier’s piece(s) had a bit more effect.

    I think Vince’s work on Torley has the makings of a substantial theological book, myself. It needs some editing, but it’s quite meaty!

  32. walto: It needs some editing, but it’s quite meaty!

    You mean it needs editing for brevity, right?

    How about meeting some theological standard? What theological books have you read so that you could compare?

  33. Erik:

    And I can say once again that Torley’s criticism hardly makes any sense…

    When did you say that before? 🙂

  34. vjtorley: When did you say that before?

    A sufficiently long time ago so that you have forgotten it and I don’t bother to dig it up, because I don’t keep the entire history of comments in my backpocket like keiths does.

    Anyway, what does it matter when I said that? It matters more whether you have started making sense.

  35. fifthmonarchyman: It’s not a evidentiary proof that God exists. It’s evidentiary proof that we don’t deserve any credit for knowing God exists.

    peace

    “shone in our hearts to give the light of the knowledge of the glory of God in the face of Jesus Christ”

    Evidentiary proof does not entail one being given credit,the presenter of the evidence if anyone deserves the credit. it is just evidence that something exists. God gives us evidence, Jesus rose from the dead, revelation.

    Wonder why God created such unworthy creatures, prone to evil.

  36. Erik: You mean it needs editing for brevity, right?

    How about meeting some theological standard? What theological books have you read so that you could compare?

    What are the theological standards?

  37. newton: What are the theological standards?

    Some theology books make sense, some don’t, and you can tell the difference when you have read a few of both kinds. Then you will know that there is a standard. Just like in science – some articles convey meaningful knowledge, some convey nonsense, and there is a way to determine which is which.

  38. Erik: Some theology books make sense, some don’t, and you can tell the difference when you have read a few of both kinds. Then you will know that there is a standard. Just like in science – some articles convey meaningful knowledge, some convey nonsense, and there is a way to determine which is which.

    Must be nice to have a correct standard, even if you can’t tell anyone else what it is.

    I’ve read some modern theology — Tillich, Buber, Niebuhr, that kind of stuff — but definitely my favorite work of theology is Placher’s The Domestication of Transcendence: How Modern Thinking About God Went Wrong. I did read David Bentley Hart’s The Experience of God but I found it deeply disappointing because he just doesn’t want to understand naturalism and attacking that straw man is a good deal of his argument. Oh — and I also thought Eagleton’s Reason, Faith, and Revolution was excellent!

    Unfortunately, I cannot claim for myself that I have a correct standard for distinguishing between theology that makes sense and theology that doesn’t. (Not that it would matter if I did have such a standard — a standard that you can’t convey to others is like Wittgenstein’s beetle in a box.)

  39. Kantian Naturalist: Must be nice to have a correct standard, even if you can’t tell anyone else what it is.

    If you deny such a standard is there, why should I waste time explaining what the standard is? I am not too enthusiastic about question begging.

    By the way, I did not say “correct standard”. I see what you are doing there.

  40. Erik: If you deny such a standard is there, why should I waste time explaining what the standard is? I am not too enthusiastic about question begging.

    The only person here begging any questions here is you. You assert that you have a standard for theological correctness but refuse to explain what it is. I’m not denying that there could be such a standard; I’m just not claiming to have one myself.

  41. Erik: Quote me on it. Let’s go over it word for word.

    Did you or did you not write the following?

    Erik: Some theology books make sense, some don’t, and you can tell the difference when you have read a few of both kinds. Then you will know that there is a standard. Just like in science – some articles convey meaningful knowledge, some convey nonsense, and there is a way to determine which is which.

    Are you know now saying that you yourself actually have no standard for determining when theological works make sense and when they don’t? So when you said this, you were just saying that if one had such a standard, one could make such determinations, but not claiming that you yourself have a standard?

  42. Kantian Naturalist: Are you know now saying that you yourself actually have no standard for determining when theological works make sense and when they don’t? So when you said this, you were just saying that if one had such a standard, one could make such determinations, but not claiming that you yourself have a standard?

    I brought an analogy how the standard works. And since it works of course I have it.

    But here’s an important note: You twisted it to “correct standard” and “standard for correctness” and then jumped on it. Instead of being a standard for correctness, it’s a standard for whether the text qualifies as theology in the first place. Whether the theology is correct or not is a different question. Certainly an interesting question, but different, and I have not touched it yet.

  43. Erik: Some theology books make sense, some don’t, and you can tell the difference when you have read a few of both kinds. Then you will know that there is a standard. Just like in science – some articles convey meaningful knowledge, some convey nonsense, and there is a way to determine which is which.

    I would think both types of books could benefit from good editing. If you have to convey nonsense at least it should get to the point.

  44. Erik: You mean it needs editing for brevity, right?

    How about meeting some theological standard? What theological books have you read so that you could compare?

    Well, I’m not exactly an expert, but I have read some Aquinas, Anselm, Leibniz, Spinoza, Hartshorne, Plantinga, and Van Inwagen. That’s probably about it. Anyhow, I do think Vince has the makings of a good book here. It might need somewhat more than light editing for brevity, however. Bops around too much, I think.

    .

Leave a Reply