A lesson in cardinality for Joe G

At his blog, Joe G. has worked himself into a lather over the cardinality (or roughly speaking, the size) of infinite sets (h/t Neil Rickert):

Of Sets, Supersets and Subsets
Oleg the Asshole, Still Choking on Sets
Of Sets and EvoTARDS
Subsets and Supersets, Revisted [sic]

In particular, Joe is convinced that the sets {0,1,2,3,…} and {1,2,3,4,…} have different cardinalities:

…the first set has at least one element that the second set does not, ie they are not equal.

So if two sets are not equal, then they cannot have the same cardinality.

As a public service, let me see if I can explain Joe’s errors to him, step by step.

First of all, Joe, sets do not have to be equal in order to have the same cardinality, as Neil showed succinctly:

I give you two sets. The first is a knife and fork. The second is a cup and saucer. Those two sets are not equal. Yet both have cardinality two.

Two sets have the same cardinality if their elements can be placed into a one-to-one correspondence. That’s the only requirement. Here is a one-to-one correspondence (or “bijection”) for Neil’s sets:

knife <–> cup
fork <–> saucer

Note that there is nothing special about that one-to-one correspondence. This one works just as well:

fork <–> cup
knife <–> saucer

It makes no difference if the elements are numbers. The same rule applies: two sets have the same cardinality if their elements can be placed into a one-to-one correspondence. Consider the sets {0,1,2} and {4,5,6}. They can be placed into the following correspondence:

0 <–> 4
1 <–> 5
2 <–> 6

As before, there is nothing special about that correspondence. This one also works:

1 <–> 4
0 <–> 5
2 <–> 6

There are six distinct one-to-one correspondences for these sets, and any one of them, by itself, is enough to demonstrate that the sets have the same cardinality.

Now take the sets {1,2,3} and {2,4,6}.  They can be placed into this one-to-one correspondence:

2 <–> 2
1 <–> 4
3 <–> 6

However, note that it’s not required that the 2 in the first set be mapped to the 2 in the second set. This one-to-one correspondence also works:

1 <–> 2
2 <–> 4
3 <–> 6

As in the previous example, there are six distinct one-to-one correspondences, and any one of them is sufficient to demonstrate that the cardinalities are the same.

Now consider the sets that are befuddling you: the infinite sets {0,1,2,3,…} and {1,2,3,4,…}. They can be placed into a one-to-one correspondence:

0 <–> 1
1 <–> 2
2 <–> 3
3 <–> 4
…and so on.

A one-to-one correspondence exists. Therefore the cardinalities are the same.

Here’s what I think is confusing you, Joe: there is a different mapping from the first set to the second that looks like this:

0 doesn’t map to anything
1 <–> 1
2 <–> 2
3 <–> 3
… and so on.

You observe that all of the elements of the second set are “used up”, while the first set still has an “unused” element — 0. You comment:

They both go to infinity but the first one starts one number before the second. That means that the first one will always have one element more than the second which means they are NOT the same size, by set standards.

But that’s silly, because you could just as easily choose a different mapping, such as:

0 doesn’t map to anything
1 doesn’t map to anything
2 doesn’t map to anything
3 <–> 1
4 <–> 2
5 <–> 3
… and so on.

Now there are three unused elements in the first set. We can also arrange for the “unused” elements to be in the second set:

nothing maps to 1
nothing maps to 2
nothing maps to 3
0 <–> 4
1 <–> 5
2 <–> 6
… and so on.

There are now three unused elements in the second set. By your logic, that would mean that the second set has a greater cardinality. It clearly doesn’t, so your logic is wrong.

You can even arrange for an infinite number of unused elements:

0 <–> 2
1 <–> 4
2 <–> 6
3 <–> 8
… and so on.

Now the odd integers are unused in the second set. Since there are now infinitely many “unused” elements in the second set, then by your logic the second set is infinitely larger than the first. Your logic is wrong, and the mathematicians are right.

Two sets have the same cardinality if they can be placed into a one-to-one correspondence. The sets {0,1,2,3,…} and {1,2,3,4,…} can be placed into such a correspondence, so they have the same cardinality.

END (Hi, KF!)

252 thoughts on “A lesson in cardinality for Joe G

  1. Joe does not have an ability to digest math. He requires a quote from the mathematical literature to be refuted.

    This should help:

    A proper subset of an infinite set can have the same cardinality as the original set.

  2. Also this:

    The cardinality of the natural numbers {1, 2, 3, 4, …..} is the same as the cardinality of the natural numbers with zero included {0, 1, 2, 3, …..}.

  3. As Joe is banned here, and therefore cannot respond, specific comments about Joe’s math should probably go to the sandbox.

    But by all means let’s discuss sets 🙂

    I myself would like to know how understanding sets relates to understanding nested hierarchies. It seems to me graph theory is a more intuitive place to start. The cool thing about living organisms is that they fall so beautifully into a tree, albeit one that is bushy near the root, and has the odd spindly lateral connection.

  4. There is simply no point arguing with a moron like Gallieni. He’s not just stupid, he’s aggressively stupid. Not only does he not know, he doesn’t know that he doesn’t know.

  5. I myself would like to know how understanding sets relates to understanding nested hierarchies.

    They’re intimately related, because each node in an evolutionary tree can be expressed as the set of its subtrees.

    For example, this tree can be compactly expressed as the following set:

    {A,{G,{{B,C,D},{E,F}}}}

  6. Well, he’s not exactly a threat to science. I do sometimes wonder whether he’s some kind of undercover COINTEL agent from the NCSE.

  7. keiths: They’re intimately related, because each node in an evolutionary tree can be expressed as the set of its subtrees.

    For example, this tree can be compactly expressed as the following set:

    {A,{G,{{B,C,D},{E,F}}}}

    Ah thanks. I think my problem with sets is that I hate curly brackets. I spend my life squinting at brackets in MatLab trying to figure out whether they should be curly or round, and not being able to see which one I’ve typed. Gimme an adjacency matrix any day.

  8. Brackets (round) are in fact used for computer-readable representations of trees. You may prefer an adjacency matrix but we in the phylogeny field would find it too big and cumbersome.

    The standard computer-readable representation of this phylogeny would be:

    (A,(G,((B,C,D),(E,F))));

    The standard was based on one invented by Christopher Meacham, which in turn was based on the relationship Cayley noted in 1857 between trees and nested-parenthesis expressions.

    The standard is described here.

  9. Of course, the sets {1,2,3,4…} and {1.0…, 2.0…., 3.0…, 4.0…} have different cardinalities. The infinite set of integers has a different cardinality from the infinite set of real numbers.

  10. This quote gives an idea where Joe is heading:

    So to sum it all up, math that doesn’t have any practical applications and uses arbitrary rules, seems very petty and meaningless. As this is a perfect example of such math.

    Translation: Math is hard and y’all are meanies!

  11. olegt:
    This quote gives an idea where Joe is heading:

    Translation: Math is hard and y’all are meanies!

    But it does have practical applications. Remember that business of nested hierarchies?

  12. olegt,

    “Fringe math,” Joe? Here is what Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy makes of it:

    Set Theory is the mathematical science of the infinite. It studies properties of sets, abstract objects that pervade the whole of modern mathematics. The language of set theory, in its simplicity, is sufficiently universal to formalize all mathematical concepts and thus set theory, along with Predicate Calculus, constitutes the true Foundations of Mathematics. As a mathematical theory, Set Theory possesses a rich internal structure, and its methods serve as a powerful tool for applications in many other fields of Mathematics. Set Theory, with its emphasis on consistency and independence proofs, provides a gauge for measuring the consistency strength of various mathematical statements.

  13. Joe G,

    Earth to keiths, I understand what you are saying. It is the same thing oleg said. And as I said that mapping is arbitrary. Why choose an arbitrary mapping when we can do a direct number by number comparison?

    It’s not an arbitrary mapping. It’s a one-to-one mapping. And the reason I chose a one-to-one mapping is that it shows exactly why your “count the leftovers” approach doesn’t work.

    If you find a one-to-one mapping between two sets, you can be sure that they have the same cardinality whether they are finite or infinite.

    One set has every number of the other set PLUS one number the other set does not contain.

    To put it more precisely, the first set includes every integer greater than or equal to 0, while the second set includes every integer greater than or equal to 1. Your mistake is in trying to treat infinity like a normal number. In effect, you are arguing that (a countable) infinity plus one is greater than (a countable) infinity. It’s not, as any mathematician (and a whole lot of non-mathematicians) can tell you.

    To say they have the same cardinality or are the size, is just subjective.

    No, it’s quite objective, because two sets are defined as having the same cardinality if their elements can be placed in a one-to-one correspondence. The nice thing about this definition is that if works for both finite and infinite sets.

    Your “count the leftovers” approach, by contrast, only works for finite sets, so mathematicians have rejected it. Mathematicians have thought about this much more carefully than you have or are able to, Joe.

    And just because you chumps buy it without question, don’t get upset with me because I can see the obvious and you cannot.

    Statements like that make you look like an ass, Joe.

    No one can measure infinity so any talk of size wrt infinity is futile. And Cantor himself said there are different degrees of infinity.

    Those two sentences contradict each other. Cantor proved, with his brilliant diagonal argument, that you can measure the cardinality of the integers (a “countable” infinity) against the cardinality of the reals (an “uncountable” infinity) and show that the latter is greater than the former.

    Now if someone had asked if {knife, fork} was the same size as {cup, saucer}, I would have said they have the same cardinality and therefor of equal size.

    That contradicts what you wrote earlier:

    So if two sets are not equal, then they cannot have the same cardinality.

    I see that you’ve gone back and edited your post to try to paper over your mistake:

    It tells you that the first set has at least one element that the second set does not, ie they are not equal- MEANING EQUAL IN SIZE MORONS.

    Anyone who knows set theory knows that sets are defined as equal if their elements are the same. Equal sets always have the same cardinality, but sets with the same cardinality are not necessarily equal. Learn some set theory, Joe.

    So please stop mixing finite sets with infinite sets. The two are not the same.

    You are the one who is taking an approach that only works with finite sets (“counting the leftovers”) and trying to apply it to infinite sets.

    Read the OP again. The one-to-one correspondence approach works with both finite and infinite sets. That’s why mathematicians use it instead of your flawed approach.

    If there were two runners, one starting at mile 0 and the other starting at mile 1. The runner at mile 1 starts running when the runner from mile 0 reaches him/ her. They then run in lockstep for infinity. At any and every point in time the runner from mile 0 will have run one more mile than the other runner.

    Yes, because every point in time is a finite point. At every finite point in time, the first runner has gone one mile farther than the second. Infinity is not a finite point, Joe, so the same reasoning does not apply to it.

    But by your logic, both runners have ran the same distance all along.

    No. By my logic, the first runner has run one more mile than the second at any finite point. Don’t confuse finite quantities with infinity.

  14. Lizzie: Ah thanks.I think my problem with sets is that I hate curly brackets.I spend my life squinting at brackets in MatLab trying to figure out whether they should be curly or round, and not being able to see which one I’ve typed.Gimme an adjacency matrix any day.

    Or some better spectacles

  15. Many of us “out here” have very limited understanding of mathematics (and are somewhat envious of those with better)

    The concepts of “zero” and “infinity” can be quite troublesome, particularly the latter

    Then again, most of us don’t descend into potty-mouthed belligerence and insistence that ignorance beats knowledge when our lack of grasp is revealed.

    Then again (again), we can always settle down with books and the internet to try to learn a bit. Or just keep quiet.

  16. I think the sticking point seems to be the fact that the integers can be both set members and ‘placeholders’ as you go along counting the members. In {0,1,2,3 …}, every member is one adrift from its ordinal position; in {1,2,3,4 …} they are the same. But you could completely randomise the sets; there is nothing that says a set must be ordered.

    Further, the behaviour of sets where the numbers are actually integers (codes for an actual number of things) is no different from one in which they are codes for something else. The numbers could equally be codes for an array of fruit held in a separate table.

    0=banana,
    1=apple,
    2=guava,
    3=grape,
    4=cherry.

    Set 1 is then {banana,apple,guava,grape…}
    Set 2 is then {apple,guava,grape,cherry…}

    Every one of those set members has a corresponding member at the same ordinal position – and so do the sets of integers, one with and one without zero (‘banana’). And this relationship doesn’t stop when you run out of ‘real’ fruit and run into the imaginary ones!

    One could even remove the ‘infinite’ part by pictorially representing the fruit on a continuous reel, and placing the reels side by side. There is a finite set of different fruit, and a finite set of results – one for each time you put your dollar in and pull the handle – but an infinite set of possible results. You can spin for infinity and will always get a member of each set, the nth member since you started playing. There will be much repetition, but each member of the result set is different – the second banana is not the first banana.

  17. I still find it non-intuitive but awesome that the set of the natural numbers has the same cardinality as the set of the rational numbers.

    And even more mind-boggling that there is no set of intermediate cardinality between those sets and the set of the reals.

    At least once I was sure I’d found one.

    Then I got distracted by perpetual motion machines.

  18. Certainly that. But I’m not sure they exist. I already have two pairs of varilux with different combinations of focal lengths.

    Age sucks.

  19. Lizzie: And even more mind-boggling that there is no set of intermediate cardinality between those sets and the set of the reals.

    As I understand it, Cantor’s Continuum Hypothesis is the thesis that there is no set of intermediate cardinality, but the CH has not been proven or disproven. The other night I was talking about this with a professor whose done some work in set theory. He suggested that the problem with the CH is that we don’t really know how far up in the order of cardinalities the power-set operation takes us, so we can’t know that the set of reals (which has the cardinality of the power-set of the naturals) is the next higher cardinality after the naturals.

  20. Good thought. Although, to be honest, my real trouble with curly braces in MatLab is that I haven’t properly figured out when you need to use them. And if I’m cannibalising some code, I sometimes don’t notice which they are.

    In fact, I tend to regard them as a kind of seasoning. If my code won’t run, I sprinkle on a few curly braces, and adjust to taste.

    It’s my secret spice weasel. Works more often than you might think.

  21. “If my code won’t run, I sprinkle on a few curly braces, and adjust to taste.”

    You are making my inner OCD programmer weep.

  22. It’s something to do with converting cell2char or char2cell (the second one I think).

    Try it! It’s better than Jalapeno!

  23. Kantian Naturalist,

    As I understand it, Cantor’s Continuum Hypothesis is the thesis that there is no set of intermediate cardinality, but the CH has not been proven or disproven.

    That’s right. In fact, it has been proven that the continuum hypothesis can be neither proven nor disproven in the context of standard set theory!

  24. From a Joe G comment underneath his latest bit of math denialism:

    Also do you think that the cardinality of the set of all whole numbers (positive and negative) is the same as as the set for only positive? That doesn’t make any sense as obvioulsy one set is twice as big as the other. I believe that is what Cantor was saying when he said some infinite cardinalities are greater than others.

    Too funny.

    Imagine being Joe. He doesn’t know set theory, he doesn’t even know the terminology, he doesn’t know what Cantor meant, he has no idea what the diagonal argument is, but he’s thought about all of this for five minutes, so he must be right and every competent mathematician in the world must be wrong.

    Joe, the integers {…,-2, -1, 0, 1, 2,…} can be placed into a one-to-one correspondence with “the set for only positive”, as you so elegantly describe it:

    0 <–> 1
    -1 <–> 2
    1 <–> 3
    -2 <–> 4
    2 <–> 5
    …and so on.

    That means they have the same cardinality, “obvioulsy”.

  25. Being a compassionate, giving kinda guy, I looked for a simple description of the properties of infinity and infinite sets to help him understand. This might be too advanced, but perhaps he’ll find that Math Is Fun!

  26. Joe,

    Ya see keiths when we say that one set is a subset of another we do NOT align them with just any member of the other set. For example take two sets:

    A={0,1,2,3,…100} and B={1,2,3,4,…100}. Set B is a proper subset of A and it aligns starting with the 1 from set B aligning with the 1 from set A. And from there every number in set B aligns with the SAME number in set A and you can then see that niothing from set B aligns with the 0 from set A.

    Invoking subsets doesn’t help, Joe. {1,2,3} is not a subset of {4,5,6}, and vice-versa. Yet they have the same cardinality, because they can be placed into a one-to-one correspondence. Mathematicians, being competent, do not use your bizarre “subset method” to assess cardinality. They also do not use your flawed “count the leftovers” method, because that doesn’t work with infinite sets. They look for one-to-one correspondences because that method actually works, for both finite and infinite sets.

    That is as if one person has one leg shorter than the others and you say “No they are the same size because I can arbitrarily add something to the bottom of this foot to make the legs the same length”. No, all you are doing is making the distance to the ground the same. The legs are still different lengths.

    Finite lengths are not infinities. Infinities are not finite. Your decidedly finite mind is failing to grasp this important distinction. Follow Patrick’s link.

  27. Joe just seems to want to use a non-standard definition of cardinality.

    I wonder if anyone else uses it?

    He seems to concede that under the definition we are using, our conclusion is correct, but useless (“fringe”).

    I’m not sure that his is any more useful, and seems redundant.

    But does anyone have an actual use for Cantor? Is there a toaster out there that wouldn’t work without it?

  28. An open message to JoeG:

    We are all having a bit of fun, laughing at what you are posting. But let me try to get serious.

    You want to look at cardinality in what seems to you to be a simple intuitive way. If that’s how you want to think about cardinality, fair enough. However, it is a central aspect of mathematics that we cannot allow ourselves to be influenced by simple intuition. For that often leads us astray. Instead, we must be sticklers for following definitions and rules of inference, even if they seem to contradict simple intuition.

    There’s some background to this. People have obviously tried looking at cardinality in accordance with simple intuition. That works with finite sets. But, when tried with infinite sets, it quickly leads to logical contradiction. The way we actually handle cardinality might look unintuitive to you, but it avoids those logic contradictions.

  29. It all boils down to infinity = infinity. Not infinity + 1, or infinity – 1.

  30. Joe’s methods don’t work, so nobody but Joe uses them. Joe’s subset method can’t even show that {knife, fork} and {cup, saucer} have the same cardinality. His “count the leftovers” method gives nonsensical answers when dealing with infinite sets, as the OP explains.

    I don’t know of any technological applications for Cantor, but he is indispensable to mathematicians, since set theory is considered to be the foundation of all mathematics.

  31. Joe’s take on infinities:

    But wait- rationals are an infinite set. And irrationals are an infinite set. Bijection says they have the same cardinality- and just so you know that is the point I am arguing. I don’t think all infinite sets are the same size. I don’t believe Cantor did either. But I don’t know of a way to tell.

    “Infinite is infinite, dude”

    I would LOVE to see one bijection that maps rational numbers onto irrational ones. Go ahead, Joe, describe the mapping. Provide a recipe for us to figure out what 1 maps onto, what is the pre-image of the square root of three, and so on.

  32. No, Joe is still as confused as ever:

    But wait- rationals are an infinite set. And irrationals are an infinite set. Bijection says they have the same cardinality- and just so you know that is the point I am arguing. I don’t think all infinite sets are the same size. I don’t believe Cantor did either. But I don’t know of a way to tell.

    “Infinite is infinite, dude”

  33. olegt,

    Hello oleg. I can name a mapping.

    f : N –> R
    f[n] = decode[n] (“9” is decoded as “,”)

    f’ : R –> N
    f'[r] = encode[r] (“,” is encoded as “9”)

    Example:
    12345945699 maps to 12345,4569
    12345,4569 maps to 12345945699

    Happy?

  34. One can have MOAR fun with Joe’s “cardinality by lineup.”

    Consider the set {0+x, 1+x, 2+x, 3+x,…}, where x is a real number. When x=0, we have {0,1,2,3,…}. When x=1, we have {1,2,3,4,…}. The great thing about parameter x is that it allows us to continuously interpolate between the two previously considered sets.

    The size of a set is “obviously” an integer number and as such it cannot change continuously. Thus, as we increase x continuously from 0 to 1, the size of the set should remain unchanged. So as we arrive at x=1, the set size is still the same as it was when we departed from 0.

    So not only do we have a bijective mapping between sets {0,1,2,3,…} and {1,2,3,4,…}, we have a continuous bijective mapping that provides a continuous interpolation between the two sets. Their sizes should certainly be the same.

  35. olegt,

    Interesting thought from Joe:

    Umm, the size of an infinite set changes continuously.

    So I take it that when x is a small positive number, the size of the set X={x,1+x,2+x,3+x,…} is slightly smaller than the size of {0,1,2,3,…}. And when x is a small negative number, it is slightly larger. Is that so?

    And what about the size of {0+ix, 1+ix, 2+ix, 3+ix,…} (where i is the imaginary unit). Is the size of that set larger or smaller than that of {0,1,2,3,…}? Or is it complex? 😮

  36. Joe,

    Why don’t you use your method (whatever it is) to compare the sizes of sets {0,1,2,3,…} and {0+x,1+x,2+x,3+x,…}, where x is a small number.

    From what I have seen so far, I would guess that the answer is “I don’t know.”

  37. Joe writes:

    Sal,

    Your input was very welcome and appreciated. On one hand I thought that I knew that all infinite sets were not equal and on the other I had my opponents yelling “infinity is infinity you IDIOT”.

    No, Joe. We were telling you that {0,1,2,3,…} has the same cardinality as {1,2,3,4,…}, and we were telling you that a countable infinity plus one has the same cardinality as a “mere” countable infinity.

    I am still trying to figure out what logical inconsistencies my definition brings about…

    Read my OP. In it, I showed how your “count the leftovers” method leads to the following absurd and contradictory results:

    1. Set 0 has a cardinality that is one greater than the cardinality of set 1.

    2. Set 0 has a cardinality that is three greater than the cardinality of set 1.

    3. Set 0 has a cardinality that is three less than the cardinality of set 1.

    4. Set 0 has a cardinality that is infinitely less than the cardinality of set 1.

    And if that isn’t obvious enough for you, consider this:

    1. Take the set {0,1,2,3,…}.

    2. Double each element. You still have the same “number” of elements, but each is twice as large as it was before, right?

    3. The new set is {0,2,4,6,…}.

    4. Now use your method to compare the original set to the new one:

    0 lines up with 0
    1 doesn’t line up with anything
    2 lines up with 2
    3 doesn’t line up with anything
    4 lines up with 4
    …and so on.

    There are an infinite number of unmatched elements, so your method tells us that the original set is infinitely larger than the new set. But we already know that the sets have the same “number” of elements, because all we did was double each element of the original set. We didn’t add any elements. Your method contradicts itself.

    Your method doesn’t work. The method of one-to-one correspondences does work. That is why no one but you uses your method, while mathematicians everywhere use the one-to-one correspondence method.

    Is it finally sinking in, Joe? (Hope springs eternal.)

  38. Better yet, Joe, why don’t you plot a graph of

    |{0,1,2,3,…}| – |{0+x, 1+x, 2+x, 3+x,…}|

    as a function of x?

    This ought to be good.

    P.S. Joe, the vertical bars denote the cardinality of the enclosed set, as I’m sure you don’t know.

  39. keiths,

    Well, Joe can’t. For a small x (say, between 0 and 1), the sets {0,1,2,3,…} and {0+x,1+x,2+x,3+x,…} have no common members. None is a proper subset of the other. So his comparison method fails.

    Thus Joe should properly answer “I don’t know.”

    The standard set theory’s answer of course is the cardinalities are the same. Because there is an obvious bijection, f(n) = n+x.

  40. Poor Joe. Sure he’s slow and obnoxious, but you can’t help feeling sorry for the guy.

    Imagining waking up every morning and realizing that you are Joe G and that you’re going to be Joe G, every day, for the rest of your life. No wonder he’s angry all the time.

    The meltdown continues:

    keiths is full of shit and proud of it

    Joe,

    That fucks up my stated methodology.

    You mean, more than it already was?

    My methodolgy states that you actually compare the two sets and the members that are the same are aligned. So 1 would always align with 1.

    I thought you might say that. That’s why I included this example at the end of my comment. Note that identical elements are lined up, just as your method requires, but it still gives the wrong answer:

    1. Take the set {0,1,2,3,…}.

    2. Double each element. You still have the same “number” of elements, but each is twice as large as it was before, right?

    3. The new set is {0,2,4,6,…}.

    4. Now use your method to compare the original set to the new one:

    0 lines up with 0
    1 doesn’t line up with anything
    2 lines up with 2
    3 doesn’t line up with anything
    4 lines up with 4
    …and so on.

    There are an infinite number of unmatched elements, so your method tells us that the original set is infinitely larger than the new set. But we already know that the sets have the same “number” of elements, because all we did was double each element of the original set. We didn’t add any elements. Your method contradicts itself.

    Why would anyone want to use your broken “method”, Joe?

  41. Joe,

    Your method fails on olegt’s example for the very same reason, plus one more:

    Then oleg the asswipe chimes in again with more nonsense:

    For a small x (say, between 0 and 1), the sets {0,1,2,3,…} and {0+x,1+x,2+x,3+x,…} have no common members. None is a proper subset of the other. So his comparison method fails.

    The correct method (the one that mathematicians use) can handle Oleg’s example regardless of the value of x. It even works if x is imaginary or complex.

    Your method can’t handle Oleg’s example unless you coddle it by forcing x to be an integer.

    Even worse, your method leads to another contradiction, just as it did on my example:

    {0+x, 1+x, 2+x, 3+x,…} has the same “number” of elements regardless of the value of x. After all, you don’t add or remove elements by changing the value of x — you just change the size of each element.

    If x=0, the set becomes {0,1,2,3,…}. If x=1, then it becomes {1,2,3,4,…}. But according to your “method”, the first set is larger than the second.

    The first set can’t simultaneously be the same size as the second and also larger than the second. Your method fails yet again by leading to a contradiction.

    And again, my comparison method works for anyone familiar with sets.

    No, your method works only if a) one set is a subset of the other, and either b) at least one of the sets is finite, or c) the user doesn’t mind getting the wrong answer again and again.

    Meanwhile, the mathematicians’ method works on both finite and infinite sets, it gives the right answer, and it doesn’t require one set to be a subset of the other.

    Who in their right mind would choose your method?

Leave a Reply