Flawed logic and bad mereology: why Feser’s first two proofs fail

In today’s post, I’m going to chop down two of Professor Feser’s proofs for God’s existence at the roots: namely, his first proof (in which Feser argues for the existence of a purely actual Being) and his second proof (in which he endeavors to show that an absolutely simple Being exists). Among Feser’s five proofs, his first proof has a special preeminence, as Feser uses it to deduce other attributes of the purely actual Being – its unity, immutability, eternity, immateriality, incorporeality, perfection, goodness, omnipotence and omniscience – which, taken together, warrant it being called “God.” Feser’s second, third, fourth and fifth proofs borrow from the arguments developed in Feser’s first proof, when deducing these same attributes, so if it turns out that the arguments Feser puts forward for these attributes rest on flawed assumptions (as I’ll show they do), then all five of Feser’s proofs of God will be flawed, in their conclusions at least.

So what’s wrong with Feser’s first two proofs? Feser’s first proof is flawed on two counts: first, his attempt to establish the existence of a Being Who is purely actual and in no way potential only manages to establish the much weaker conclusion that there exists something which doesn’t need anything outside it to “hold it together” as a being, and which doesn’t need to be “switched on” (or actualized) by anything else, either in order to exist, or in order to ground the existence of other things – a description which could apply to material objects. Additionally, Feser’s argument that there cannot be more than one purely actual Being is badly flawed, as it trades on an ambiguity in the words “privation” and “lack”: not having a perfection is only a defect if having that perfection is part of one’s nature. (A bird that lacks wings is deficient; a man who lacks wings is not.)

Feser’s second proof of God’s existence, which argues for the existence of an absolutely simple Being, is equally flawed – in this case, by bad mereology. (Mereology is the branch of philosophy which deals with parts and wholes.) Incredibly, nowhere in his proof – indeed, nowhere in his entire book, or in any of his other books – does Feser even bother to define what it means for something to be a part of a whole, and in any case, his argument proves much less than Feser would like it to: all it shows is that there is a Being whose essence is not composed of parts that are ontologically prior to the whole they comprise. However, even a Being with a simple essence could (if it is a personal agent) nonetheless have properties, extrinsic to His essence, which He freely generates by Himself, when creating things. Alternatively (if it is an impersonal entity), it might have other properties which arise from its essence and are therefore ontologically posterior to its essence. In any event, neither of Feser’s first two proofs demonstrate the existence of a Being which is distinct from the material world, and for this reason, they cannot take us to God.

What about Feser’s remaining proofs – his third, fourth and fifth arguments? Unfortunately, in order to arrive at the conclusion that there is a God (and not just a First Cause), they all rely on the critical assumption (which Feser fails to justify) that the First Cause is purely actual. For that reason alone, they fail as proofs, in their current form. Whether a revamped version of these arguments can succeed in establishing the existence of God is a topic I’ll discuss in a future post.

Readers may be wondering why I, as a religious believer, am attacking Feser’s first two proofs with such gusto. My reasons can be summed up in four words: Divine and human freedom. If you accept Feser’s argument that there exists a purely actual, absolutely simple Being, then two things follow: first, you have no more freedom than a character in a novel does, which means that your Maker cannot hold you morally accountable for your misdeeds, even if other people do; and second, the Being Who created you lacks the capacity to make free choices (scroll down to section 4, on God’s Will), as it has no potentialities which it is capable of realizing. I’ve explained why these conclusions follow from Feser’s arguments in my previous posts (see here and here), so I won’t repeat myself here. Since I believe that we are morally accountable for our actions to everyone (including God), and since I believe that God would have had to actualize His potential to create – something Feser says a purely actual Being cannot do – when He freely chose to make this world, then I have a strong interest in discrediting Feser’s first two proofs of God’s existence, as someone who believes that both God and and human beings possess genuine, libertarian free will.

Before I continue, I’d like to say that I have the greatest respect for Professor Feser, despite my differences with him. In any vigorous academic controversy, there is always the potential for mutual misunderstanding, so I would like to state here that I have made every effort to represent Feser’s views (and his reasons for holding them) as accurately as possible. If Dr. Feser notices any inaccuracies, then I would welcome his correction.

As today’s post will be a lengthy one, I’ve decided to set up a main menu, which will allow readers to navigate their way backwards and forwards with total freedom, when perusing it.

MAIN MENU

A. INTRODUCTION
1. The centrality of Feser’s first proof: how all his other proofs rely on it

B. FLAWS WHICH UNDERCUT FESER’S FIRST PROOF
2. The logic of Feser’s argument for the existence of a First Actualizer

3. What Feser gets right and wrong about infinite regresses and hierarchical causal series

4. Feser’s flawed argument that the First Actualizer must be purely actual

5. Feser’s flawed argument that there can only be ONE First Actualizer

C. FLAWS WHICH UNDERCUT FESER’S SECOND PROOF
6. Bad Mereology: Feser’s failure to define what it means for something to be a part of a whole

7. Feser’s flawed argument for the existence of an Absolutely Simple Being

8. Feser’s argument that there can only be ONE Absolutely Simple Being

D. FLAWS WHICH RUIN ALL OF FESER’S FIVE PROOFS
9. Why Feser’s proofs that the First Actualizer must be immutable, eternal, immaterial, incorporeal, perfect, good, omnipotent and omniscient all fail

===================================================================

A. INTRODUCTION


RETURN TO MAIN MENU

1. The centrality of Feser’s first proof: how all his other proofs rely on it

Liverpool Metropolitan Cathedral at dusk. Note the flying buttresses, which uphold the tall central pillar. Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

Feser’s five proofs for God’s existence are by no means independent of one another: rather, they resemble a single tall pillar, which is supported at its base by four additional buttresses. What I intend to show here is that the pillar itself is an Aristotelian one: Feser’s proofs all deduce key attributes of the Being they end up calling “God” from the Aristotelian premise that a purely actual Being exists. Without this premise, Feser’s arguments are incapable of taking us to a Being whom we would call God. The following brief excerpts from Feser’s second, third, fourth and fifth proofs of God’s existence will serve to illustrate my point.

In his formal statement of his second, Neo-Platonic proof, Feser includes the following premise, which harks back to his first, Aristotelian proof of God’s existence:

35. A purely actual cause must be perfect, omnipotent, fully good and omniscient. (2017, p. 82)

In his formal statement of his third, Augustinian proof, Feser once again includes a premise which appeals to conclusions reached in his Aristotelian proof of God’s existence:

26. What is purely actual must also be omnipotent, fully good, immutable, immaterial, incorporeal, and eternal.

In his fourth, Thomistic proof, after having established the existence of a Being Who is Pure Existence itself, and after having deduced that such a Being must be purely actual, Feser then invokes conclusions previously reached in his Aristotelian proof:

33. Whatever is purely actual must be immutable, eternal, immaterial, incorporeal, perfect, omnipotent, fully good, intelligent, and omniscient.

Finally, in his fifth, Rationalist proof, after having argued for the existence of a necessary Being, and after having reasoned that such a Being would have to be purely actual, simple and identical with its own act of existence, Feser draws upon the Aristotelian proof one last time, in order to deduce additional divine attributes:

Something which is purely actual, absolutely simple or non-composite, and something which just is subsistent existence itself must also be immutable, eternal, immaterial, incorporeal, perfect, omnipotent, fully good, intelligent, and omniscient.

The upshot of all this is that if Feser’s Aristotelian argument for a purely actual Being is shown to be flawed, then Feser’s five proofs provide us with no reason for thinking that an immutable, eternal, immaterial, incorporeal, perfect, omnipotent, fully good, intelligent, and omniscient Being exists – and hence, no reason for thinking that God exists. Without a revamp, they all fail.

===================================================================

B. FLAWS WHICH UNDERCUT FESER’S FIRST PROOF

Summary of My Argument: In this section, I’ll be arguing that Feser’s first proof of the existence of God is flawed on two counts: it fails to establish the existence of a Purely Actual Being, and it fails to show that such a Being must be unique. As we’ll see, Feser’s argument for a purely actual Being requires the existence of a hierarchical series of efficient causes, each of which actualizes the existence of its effect, and the examples he cites in his book don’t fit this description: either they’re material causes (rather than efficient ones) or they don’t actualize the existence of their effects, but merely hold them in place. In any case, all Feser’s philosophical argument demonstrates is that there exists a First Actualizer which does not require anything else in order to exist, or in order to ground the existence of other things. Feser’s attempts to show that such a Being must be utterly devoid of all potentialities, even with regard to the activities which it is capable of performing, turn out to rely on vaguely worded metaphysical principles and questionable assumptions about parts (which I’ll discuss further in section C), which Feser does not justify. Even worse, Feser’s argument for the uniqueness of this purely actual Being rests on faulty logic, as it trades on an ambiguity in the terms “privation” and “lack,” which may denote either a perfection which a being does not have, or one which a being could and should have (i.e. an unrealized potential, which no purely actual Being would possess). Since the aim of Feser’s first proof is to show that there exists one and only one purely actual Being, and to then use its pure actuality as a springboard to deduce this Being’s other attributes (which make it worthy of being called “God”), I am forced to conclude that Feser’s first proof of God’s existence is irremediably flawed.


RETURN TO MAIN MENU

2. The logic of Feser’s argument for the existence of a First Actualizer

Feser’s argument for the existence of an Ultimate Actualizer (2017, pp. 35-36) can be divided into two parts: first, he attempts to establish that any change occurring in the world requires an actual cause (premises 1 to 5), and then he proceeds to argue that any change has to take place within some thing, or substance, whose existence presupposes the existence of a purely actual Being (premises 6 to 15).

A short note on Feser’s first five premises

Radioactive decay, such as the alpha-decay of a Pb-210 atom into an atom of Hg-206, is often (mistakenly) held to be an example of an uncaused change. Image courtesy of Inductiveload and Wikipedia.

To give credit where credit is due, I have to say that Feser’s discussion of change in his book is very thorough: he forestalls all of the objections that have been raised against Aristotle’s argument for the existence of an Unmoved Mover (or as Feser would prefer to say, an Unactualized Actualizer).

The most fundamental objection that could be made to any such argument is to deny the reality of change itself. Feser responds to the “block universe” objection (based on Minkowski’s interpretation of Einstein’s theory of relativity) that in a four-dimensional universe where time is treated as just an extra dimension, change is an illusion, by pointing out that even if the theory of relativity can account for physical change without having to treat it as objectively real, it still fails to rule out the occurrence of psychological change (e.g. when someone who was previously skeptical of the theory of relativity comes to believe it is true). This rebuttal amounts to a “Cartesianization” of Aristotle’s argument: if I can be deceived about the occurrence of change, then my being undeceived is itself a change. In effect, this reduces Aristotle’s Unmoved Mover to the status of an Undeceived Deceiver (or Undeceiver)! Much more apropos is Feser’s second rebuttal of the “block universe” objection: even if change turns out not to be objectively real, the actualization of potential certainly is, because the very existence of a thing (such as a body) involves the actualization of its potential. (For instance, if the body is composed of parts, then these parts have the potential to disintegrate: in other words, the body is capable of non-existence.)

Feser addresses the objections that Newton’s First Law of Motion makes no mention of causes, and that quantum mechanics does away with causes at the submicroscopic level, by pointing out that these are purely mathematical descriptions of reality, which make no attempt to capture the notion of a cause (2017, pp. 51-54). So far, so good. However, with regard to Newton’s First Law, I think Feser would have been better off arguing that what Newton really showed was that a change in a body’s position, as such, is not a real change in the body itself, which needs some Actualizer to bring it about: rather, it is only a change in a body’s velocity that needs to be accounted for, in terms of the external forces accelerating that body. An Aristotelian might object that even when a body moves through space at constant velocity, it will still (eventually) come under the influence of forces that were not acting on it previously, as it approaches other bodies – but in that case, the body’s velocity will change, and that (not the body’s moving at constant velocity) is what we need to account for. The key point here is that there is no need to regard a body’s movement at constant velocity as a new actualization of its potential, which needs to be explained by some Actualizer. Only acceleration requires such an Actualizer.

With regard to radioactive decay, which is often held to be uncaused, Feser argues that even if it is a non-deterministic event, it still requires a cause. That cause, he suggests, may be either the thing that originally generated the atom which is now decaying (a bad move, in my opinion, as it pushes the cause back into the distant past) orwhatever it is that keeps the … atom in existence here and now” (2017, p. 55). The latter suggestion makes more sense, but it seems to me that Feser could have simply appealed to the existence of the quantum vacuum at this point: radioactive decay is caused by the tunnelling of a particle out of the nucleus, which in turn occurs because the particle is able to borrow energy from the surrounding quantum vacuum: this borrowed energy can thus be described as the efficient cause of the nucleus’s decay. Likewise, virtual particles (which randomly fluctuate into and out of existence over very short periods of time) do not arise out of nowhere, but out of the quantum field which they are associated with; this field may therefore be called their efficient cause.

Feser also successfully addresses the scientific objection that there is always a slight time delay between cause and effect by pointing out (2017, pp. 61-62) that there is no such time delay when the cause and effect are contiguous (e.g. when the throwing of a brick breaks a glass, or when a stick moves a stone which it makes contact with), because in these cases, what we have are not two “loose and separate” events with no “necessary connection” holding between them (as Hume famously envisaged), but rather, two parts of one and the same event (e.g. the brick’s smashing of the glass, or the stick’s impact on the stone) – namely, the cause’s bringing about of the effect. And even if this event takes place over a short interval of time, this in no way undermines the claim that the cause and effect are simultaneous; all it shows is that the action of the cause is not instantaneous.

Einstein’s theory of relativity is sometimes invoked as an objection to the notion that a cause and its immediate effect are simultaneous, as the simultaneity of two events depends on the observer’s frame of reference, according to Einstein’s theory. Feser smacks down this objection by noting that the relativity of simultaneity only applies to two spatially separated events, whereas in the case we are considering, there is one event occurring at a single spatial location (2017, p. 63). Hence the objection is irrelevant.

All in all, Feser does a pretty good job of rebutting the common objections to Aristotle’s Argument from Motion, but in doing so, he transforms it into an entirely different kind of argument: no longer is it an argument about change but about being, instead. On Feser’s rendition of the argument, it is the actualization of being which needs to be explained. Which is all well and good: but that then renders the first five premises of Feser’s argument redundant.

A curious feature of Feser’s Aristotelian proof: the first five premises are redundant!

One of Feser’s favorite examples: a coffee cup resting on a desk.

Feser spends the first five pages of his Aristotelian proof (2017, pp. 17-21) trying to establish that change is an objective feature of the world, and that changes requires a changer, plus no less than 15 pages rebutting objections relating to allegedly uncaused changes occurring in the natural world, as well as accusations that his proof is based on outdated science (2017, pp. 46-60). So it is quite astonishing when Feser abruptly changes gear on page 21, and invites his readers to consider instead the example of a coffee cup resting on a desk (which is supported by the floor, the foundation of your house, and ultimately the Earth itself), in order to illustrate the notion of a hierarchical series of causes, whose members possess only derived causal power, with the exception of the first member, whose causal power is built-in or inherent (2017, p. 24). Feser explains that what is really significant in this illustration is that potentials are being actualized, even if no change occurs, and he confesses that the examples which he used of change, earlier on in the chapter, were intended merely to convey to readers the idea of a potential which is incapable of actualizing itself:

What we call a hierarchical series of causes is quite different. Here every cause other than the first has its causal power only in a derivative way. Thus the desk, floor and foundation have no power to hold aloft the coffee cup except insofar as they derive it from the earth this whole series rests on. This takes us beyond what we would ordinarily think of as change, because we would ordinarily think of the sequence of the cup, desk, floor, foundation, and earth as simultaneous. But what matters is that we still do have the actualization of potentials, the notion of which was introduced as a way of making sense of change. The potential of the cup to be three feet off the ground is actualized by the desk, the desk’s potential to hold the coffee cup aloft is actualized by the floor, and so forth. (2017, p. 25)

We can therefore safely ignore the first six premises of Feser’s argument, which conclude that change is caused by something already actual (premise 5), and that the occurrence of any change C presupposes some thing or substance S which changes (premise 6). For Feser’s argument, in the end, is not about change, but about being: what he is trying to show is that there is a Thing (or Being) which actualizes the potential for existence of all other things, and that this Being is itself purely actual. And in order to do that, he doesn’t need to invoke the occurrence of change in the world; all he needs to point out is that some things (or substances) have the potential not to exist – which implies that they also have a potential to exist, which is currently being actualized (obviously, or they wouldn’t be here).

A response to an objection raised by Bradley Bowen

Christine Jorgensen (born George William Jorgensen Jr.), the first person to become widely known in the United States for having sex reassignment surgery. Jorgensen’s sex change surgery creates an apparent difficulty for Feser’s account of change as the actualization of a potential, if we define “potential” as a natural tendency, as the physical change wrought by sex change surgery is not realizing a natural tendency: it requires radical human intervention. Image courtesy of Maurice Seymour and Wikipedia.

Over at the Secular Outpost, philosopher Bradley Bowen objects (see here and here) that the terms “potential” and “thing or substance” are not properly defined by Feser, in premise 6 of his argument. Bowen’s objection is a very powerful one, but I think it can be met. So on Feser’s behalf, I’d like to propose a definition of “substance“: a particular entity with causal powers – specifically, a mind or a material entity (e.g. a physical object, or an agglomeration), or even a mental content (e.g. a thought, a memory, or an afterimage), but not an abstract entity (e.g. happiness) or a generic substance (e.g. sulfur, water or human DNA). On page 75 of his book, Feser approvingly quotes a statement from philosopher William Vallicella’s book, A Paradigm Theory of Existence: Onto-Theology Vindicated (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2002, p. 233) to the effect that “everything is either a mind, or a content in a mind, or a physical entity, or an abstract entity,” and he goes on to add that abstract entities are causally inert – which would automatically rule them out as candidates for an Uncaused Cause. Generic substances such as water would be ruled out for similar reasons: not being individuals, they are incapable of causing anything. This agglomeration of water here can (if it is big enough and traveling fast enough) cause a tsunami, but water in general cannot.

On the definition I have proposed above, which I think Feser would endorse, the following entities proposed by Bowen would count as things or substances: God (bearing in mind that for Feser, God is one of a kind), angels, persons, minds, clouds, and even the pain I feel in my right foot, but not coffee (which is generic rather than particular), gravity (ditto), the number three (an abstract object), the color red (ditto, although a red afterimage would count as a thing), space and time (arguably, both abstract objects, and in any case, causally inert). Although coffee and gravity do not qualify as things, this cup of coffee and the Earth’s gravity would certainly qualify as things, on the definition I am proposing.

Regarding the definition of “potential,” Bowen objects that logical possibility is too broad a definition, as it fails to explain why we say that while a hot cup of coffee has the potential to become a cold cup of coffee, it does not have the potential to become chicken soup or gasoline. On the other hand, a definition of “potential” in terms of a thing’s natural tendency is too narrow to cover all cases of change: for example, a person undergoing a sex change operation, or cosmetic surgery, is not realizing a natural tendency in the process, since without deliberate human intervention, that person’s body would never normally develop in the manner which they are trying to achieve. Again, some changes are brought about by sheer luck, rather than any natural tendency: sometimes people who are terrible actors go on to become movie stars, because they just happened to be in the right place at the right time.

But there is an intermediate kind of possibility between logical possibility and the possession of a natural tendency: physical possibility. And in a comment made on January 6, 2018, Bowen agreed that “[p]hysical possibility does seem like a close match to what Feser has in mind.”

I suspect, however, that Feser’s definition is somewhat broader than physical possibility, and that he would want to include metaphysical possibility as a kind of potential, since he would not wish to rule out in advance the existence of immaterial minds, such as angels, to whom the concept of physical possibility would not apply. Such minds might even be capable of performing feats which are physically impossible, but not metaphysically impossible: for instance, they may be able to lower the entropy of a closed system, or perhaps even turn a rod into a snake (to recall one of the more colorful miracles narrated in the book of Exodus, which even Pharaoh’s magicians were said to be capable of duplicating), but not to take human beings back into their own past (a metaphysically absurd scenario that gives rise to Einstein’s famous “grandmother paradox”). It is worth noting that Feser’s Aristotelian argument for God’s existence makes no advance commitment to the existence of immaterial minds; but by the same token, he would certainly not wish to rule them out, either.

Feser’s nine-step argument for a purely actual actualizer

A visual proof of Pythagoras’ Theorem. Image courtesy of William B. Faulk and Wikipedia.

We can now jettison premises 1 to 6 of Feser’s Aristotelian proof for God’s existence, and proceed instead from the premise: Let S be some thing or substance, understood as a particular entity with causal powers. We’ll call this premise 6A. Feser’s nine-step argument for the existence of a purely actual actualizer goes as follows:

[6A. Let S be some thing or substance – i.e. a particular entity with causal powers.]

7. The existence of S at any given moment itself presupposes the concurrent actualization of S’s potential for existence [where “potential” signifies “metaphysical possibility.”]

8. So, any substance S has at any moment some actualizer A of its existence.

9. A’s own existence at the moment it actualizes S itself presupposes either (a) the concurrent actualization of its own potential for existence or (b) A’s being purely actual.

10. If A’s existence at the moment it actualizes S presupposes the concurrent actualization of its own potential for existence, then there exists a regress of concurrent actualizers that is either infinite or terminates in a purely actual actualizer.

11. But such a regress of concurrent actualizers would constitute a hierarchical causal series, and such a series cannot regress infinitely.

12. So, either A itself is a purely actual actualizer or there is a purely actual actualizer which terminates the regress that begins with the actualization of A.

13. So, … the existence of S at any given moment presupposes the existence of a purely actual actualizer. [Feser actually writes: “the occurrence of C and thus the existence of S,” but as we’ve seen, the argument still stands, even if we remove mention of any change C.]

14. So, there is a purely actual actualizer.

Feser’s fallacy

That’s Feser’s argument for a purely actual actualizer, in a nutshell. The metaphysically controversial premises are premises 9 and 11. As I’ll explain below, I accept premise 11, but I think premise 9 is mistaken, because it poses a false dichotomy: instead of saying that the actualizer A’s own existence presupposes either (a) the concurrent actualization of its own potential for existence or (b) A’s being purely actual, we should say that it presupposes either (a) the concurrent actualization of its own potential for existence or (b) A’s not having a potential for existence that needs to be actualized. On the second alternative, A would need nothing outside itself to hold it together as a being, and A would not need to be “switched on” (or actualized) by anything else, either in order to exist, or in order to ground the existence of other things. However, A’s not having a potential for existence that needs to be actualized is not the same as A’s being purely actual – a point which undercuts Feser’s attempts to deduce the attributes of the Uncaused Cause from its being purely actual. For all we know, a being whose existence does not need to be actualized by anything else might turn out to be a material object, and nothing more – for example, a quantum field, or something like that.

To his credit, Dr. Feser is aware of this objection, and tries to rebut it in his book. Below, in section 4, we’ll examine Feser’s attempts to show that a Being whose essence is purely actual must also be actual in every other respect, and why these attempts are unsuccessful.

===================================================================


RETURN TO MAIN MENU

3. What Feser gets right and wrong about infinite regresses and hierarchical causal series


Why hierarchical causal series require a first cause

For the record, I happen to think Feser is right in distinguishing between hierarchical causal series (where the intermediate members of the series exercise causal power in a purely derivative sense) and linear causal series (where each member exercises causal power in its own right – Feser gives the example of coffee in a cup being cooled by the surrounding air, which has been cooled by the air conditioner, which was turned on earlier by you). Feser points out that linear causal series don’t need a first member. To cite a well-worn example from Aristotle: sons are sired by their fathers, who are sired by their fathers, and for all we know, this may have been going on for all eternity. However, Feser insists that since the intermediate causes in a hierarchical series possess their power in a purely derivative sense, this kind of series requires a first member that possesses causal power inherently – for if there were no such member, the series as a whole would possess no causal power whatsoever. That doesn’t necessarily mean that a hierarchical causal series needs to come to a terminus at some point: Feser is willing to allow (2017, p. 24) that the first member of the series, rather than being at the top of a finite series, could equally well be standing outside an infinite series of hierarchical causes, directly imparting causal power to each member of the series.

Why Feser’s coffee cup is not a hierarchical causal series, and why that matters

Latte, with latte art, in a 12 oz. ceramic mug. Courtesy of Coffeecupgals and Wikipedia.

One of the examples Feser draws upon in his argument for a purely actual Being is that of the coffee in a cup, which depends for its existence on the various substances which make it up, such as water, which is in turn dependent on its constituent hydrogen and oxygen atoms, which in turn depend on the subatomic particles that make them up.

What I would like to point out here is that while the series is indeed hierarchical, it is not a causal series, in the sense required by Feser, which corresponds to what Aristotle called an efficient cause. Recall that in Feser’s argument, each cause actualizes the existence of its effect – in other words, it does something to bring it about. That is precisely what an efficient cause does: it’s a “doing” cause, just as a verb is a “doing” word (most of the time, anyway). And in ordinary English parlance, whenever we speak of A as being the cause of B, we mean the efficient cause. Feser appears to acknowledge in his book (2017, p. 55) that the causal series he has in mind is a series of efficient causes, when he refers to “whatever it is that keeps the Pb210 atom in existence here and now” as a “deeper efficient cause.”

However, the dependence of coffee upon its chemical constituents is a dependence of a different sort, which Aristotle referred to as material causality. A material cause can be defined as the matter or substance which constitutes a thing which is being changed, or otherwise actualized. For a table, that might be wood; and for the coffee in a cup, that would be the various chemicals (including water) which make up the coffee. Unlike an efficient cause, which is external to the thing it actualizes, the material cause is internal: it is simply the substrate underlying the thing’s actualization.

The first point I wish to make here is that a hierarchical series of material causes might turn out to be infinite: the coffee in a cup could be dependent on its various chemical constituents, which are dependent on the atoms of which they are composed, which are in turn dependent on the subatomic particles that comprise them, and so on ad infinitum. The supposition that a lump of matter is divided into infinitely many parts may strike many people as uncongenial, but unless we accept the traditional arguments against the possibility of an actual infinite (and Feser himself is somewhat agnostic about these arguments, which he nowhere appeals to in his book), then it seems we cannot exclude this possibility.

The second point I’d like to make is that Feser’s argument for a purely actual Being requires the existence of a hierarchical series of efficient causes, each of which actualizes the existence of its effect. It is this kind of series which Feser argues cannot be infinite, as it requires an ultimate member which possesses causal power in its own right. But in a series of material causes, the various component parts do not exercise any causal power upon the whole which they comprise: for instance, the hydrogen and oxygen atoms in a water molecule may act upon each other, but they do not “act upon” the molecule as a whole. Because the various components of a thing, at any given level, do not exercise causal power upon the next level up, there is no need to postulate an ultimate source of their causal power, such as a “bottom level” of material reality. There might be one, and there might not. We don’t know.

The upshot is that the illustration of the coffee in a cup doesn’t help Feser’s case. We need to find a better illustration. Feser provides two illustrations which are valid examples of efficient causality, but as we’ll see, they don’t help his case, either.

Coffee cups,lamps and supports

Feser uses the example of a lamp above your head, which is held up by a chain, and ultimately by the Earth, to illustrate his argument that a hierarchical series of causes must have a first member, which possesses causal power in its own right. Image courtesy of Kyle Pearce, Slick Lighting and Wikipedia.

Feser appeals to two examples to bolster his case that an infinite regress of concurrent actualizers requires a first member: first, a coffee cup resting upon a desk, which is supported by the floor, which is in turn supported by the foundation of a house, which is supported by the Earth itself; and second, a lamp above your head, which is held up by a chain, which is held up by a fixture screwed into the ceiling, which in turn is held up by the walls of your house, which are supported by the foundation, which is held up by the Earth. Neither of these examples helps Feser’s case.

First, let us suppose, as Feser does, that the series of causes is indeed a hierarchical series. Even if that were true, Feser himself admits in his book (2017, p. 26) that they do not constitute examples of one thing maintaining another thing in existence: as he puts it, only in the case we discussed above, of the coffee in the cup, is it “the very existence of a thing that is at issue rather than merely its particular location.” The desk on which the coffee coup rests keeps it here, but it does not keep it in being. The same goes for the chain that holds up the lamp above your head.

Second, careful consideration of the two examples cited by Feser reveals that each of them is actually a linear causal series, as far as the actual exercise of causal power is concerned. At first blush, it might seem as though what the desk does to the coffee cup it supports is to provide a stable surface for it to rest on. Likewise, what the chain does is to provide a stable attachment for the lamp connected to it. But while these expressions accurately describe the function of the desk and the chain, they don’t tell us what action each performs, in order to carry out this function: “providing stability” is not the name of an action as such. Now, however we describe this action (and I don’t wish to get technical here), the important point is that it is carried out by the molecules at the interface between the supporting object and the object it supports. The key point here is that molecules do not derive their causal powers from anything else in the cosmos – and certainly not from the Earth. For instance, the molecules on the surface of the desk hold up the coffee cup by virtue of their electrostatic properties, which they possess inherently. And when each of the members of a causal chain exercises causal powers in its own right, then what we have is a linear causal series, not a hierarchical one.

It is of course true that if the foundation of the house were suddenly to disappear, the desk would no longer support the coffee cup, and the chain would no longer hold up the lamp. But it would be a mistake to infer from this fact that the foundation is doing something to the desk and the coffee cup, or to the chain and lamp, to keep them in place. It isn’t acting on any of these things. All that the foundation interacts with are the surfaces in contact with it: namely, the floor and the walls. Likewise, it would be a mistake to think that the foundation of the house somehow transfers causal power to the desk, via the floor, or that it transfers causal power to the chain via the walls, ceiling and light fixture. There is no “transfer” here: for what exactly is it that’s supposed to “pass through” the walls and the floor to the lamp and the coffee cup? Some flow of energy, perhaps? Then why can’t we measure any such mysterious flow? And how does it manage to pass through insulated material? Is it gravity, then? But in that case, it needs no intermediate causes: the Earth alone is massive enough to do the job, and it certainly doesn’t attract a coffee cup by imparting some mysterious downward-pulling power to the foundation, floor and desk upon which it rests.

What I am suggesting is that in the examples cited by Feser, we have been misled by the way we ordinarily describe what’s going on, into thinking that some kind of occult “causal power” is traveling from the Earth to the lamp and the coffee cup. In fact, there is no transmission: indeed, even to call it a linear causal series is incorrect. Rather, what we have here is a set of entirely separate cause and effect pairs (namely, the surfaces which happen to be in contact with one another), which, taken as an ensemble, do a pretty good job of holding up the coffee cup and the lamp.

The foundation falls away: do Feser’s two causal series really behave like linear causal series?

A lodestone, or natural magnet, attracting iron nails. The magnetized nails can in turn pick up other nails, or iron filings. What’s interesting is that the nails retain their magnetism for a short while, even when the magnet is removed. Image courtesy of Fred Anzley Annet and Wikipedia.

Feser may object that whereas in a linear causal series, the members of the series will continue acting even when the earlier members of the series cease to do so (e.g. the air conditioner will keep working even if the person who switches it on suddenly dies of a heart attack), this is not the case for the two examples he cites: take away the foundation of the house, and the coffee cup and lamp will both fall from their present positions. But here, I think Feser is making a false generalization. For a linear series of causes, it is not always the case that the removal of an earlier cause will leave the operation of subsequent causes unimpeded. Even in a linear series, the sudden removal of one member of the series may cause subsequent members of the series to lose their inherent causal power almost immediately. In Feser’s own illustration of a linear series, if the air conditioner stops working, the air in the room will eventually heat up again, warming the coffee. And there are much better examples: think of a magnet which picks up a nail, which in turn attracts some iron filings. For a brief time, the nail’s power to attract iron filings is inherent (albeit very weak and evanescent), as shown by the fact that if the magnet is suddenly removed, the nail will remain magnetic for a short while, and will continue to attract the iron filings. Here, then, we have a linear causal series, where the removal of a cause higher up the chain (namely, the magnet) has an almost immediate effect, further down the chain. And so it is with the desk on which the coffee cup rests: if the foundation of the house supporting the desk is suddenly removed, it will start to fall almost immediately.

This is very important, for it has bearing on my next point: namely, that the kind of hierarchical causal series which Feser requires for his argument to work, cannot exist in the natural world.

Why simultaneity matters

While Feser allows (2017, p. 24) that even a hierarchical causal series might be infinite in length, with the First Cause standing above all the intermediate members and sustaining each of them, he does not rule out the possibility that the first member of a hierarchical causal series may turn out to be a remote cause, at the top of a very long but finite series. This is an important point, because Feser is emphatic that the first cause is no mere Initiator – a first cause that may have kicked the bucket long before its ultimate effect is brought into being – but a very actively involved concurrent cause, as he insists in premise 9 of his argument. As he puts it (2017, p. 28): “for a thing to exist at any particular moment requires that it be actualized at that moment, at least if it is the sort of thing which has the potential either to exist or not to exist.”

In order for the first member of a very long hierarchical series to be concurrent with its ultimate effect, it isn’t enough, as Feser appears to suggest on pages 60 to 63 of his book, that the First Cause’s act of bringing about the effect take place over an interval of time rather than an instant: for it could still be the case that the action of the First Cause takes place over the time interval from t0 to t1, while the occurrence of the ultimate effect in the series takes place over a later time interval from t2 to t3, which would mean that the First Cause may or may not still exist when the effect occurs: it might have dropped dead or vanished into thin air. This is precisely the kind of scenario Feser wants to rule out, in the case of a hierarchical causal series.

Fishermen’s boat stranded in Kallady, Sri Lanka, by the 2004 tsunami. The tsunami which hit Sri Lanka was caused by a magnitude-9.2 earthquake that occurred in Aceh, Indonesia, two hours previously. The quake itself lasted no more than ten minutes.

Nor will it help to assert, as Feser does (2017, pp. 62-63) that the links in a hierarchical causal series all form part of one big event: even if that were so, it in no way entails that the various causes contributing to the event all overlap in time. Maybe they will and maybe they won’t. For that matter, you could describe the approach of a tsunami from hundreds of kilometers away as one “big event,” but the earthquake which triggered it may be over, by the time the tidal wave generated hits the remote shore (see the picture above, which depicts the result of the 2004 Aceh tsunami, generated by an earthquake which lasted no more than ten minutes but generated a tidal wave that took two hours to reach Sri Lanka). So while Feser may be correct in writing that “what makes a causal series hierarchical than linear is not simultaneity per se, but rather the fact that all the members in such a series other than the first have their causal power have their causal power in a derivative or instrumental rather than inherent or ‘built-in’ way” (2017, p. 63), it seems to me that he is still committed to the simultaneity of cause and effect, in a hierarchical causal series. Thus if the action of the First Cause were to take place over a time interval from t0 to t1, the occurrence of the ultimate effect in the series would have to take place over the same time interval, from t0 to t1.

Now, we happen to live in a cosmos where causal influences of any kind take time to propagate over any distance. Since hierarchical causal series require strict simultaneity of cause and effect (as I have argued above), the only such series in the natural world must be very short ones, involving two objects in contact with one another – for example, a ball breaking a window. But even this kind of causality could not possibly allow one object to maintain another object in existence, as the former object is in contact with only the surface of the latter object, leaving the other parts untouched. Within our cosmos, then, it appears that one object never actually maintains another object in existence. (Incidentally, one organism’s transferring vital nutrients to a dependent organism is not the same as maintaining that organism in existence, as (a) it would not perish immediately if the transfer were halted, and (b) the nutrients only benefit it once they are inside its own body, and hence part of it.)

What does that mean for Feser’s argument? As we’ve seen, Feser hasn’t established the existence of a purely actual Being; all he’s shown is that there is some being whose existence does not need to be actualized by anything else. I pointed out above that such a being might turn out to be a material object, and we can now see that material objects are never maintained in existence by other natural objects, in any case. Feser may wish to argue that material objects, whether they be people, pandas, poplars or particles, still require a Transcendent Cause to maintain them in existence, and I believe he is right on this point. But he hasn’t demonstrated that yet, and it is incumbent on him to do so.

Linear causes can be instrumental, too

Dominoes waiting to fall: each is an instrument of the agent who set them up. Image courtesy of Enoch Lai and Wikipedia.

Before I conclude my discussion of hierarchical and linear causal series, I’d like to address the manner in which items in these series can be instruments. In his discussion of hierarchical causal series, Feser writes:

To characterize something as an instrumental cause is … to say that it derives its causal power from something else. (2017, pp. 65-66)

A hierarchical series without a first member would be like an instrument that is not the instrument of anything, a series of causes which have derivative causal powers without anything from which to derive it. (2017, p. 64)

On this point, I believe Feser’s reasoning is sound. However, what Feser overlooks is the fact that the causes in a linear causal series are also capable of being instrumental, if they happen to be finite, and if the first cause in the series is an agent, who is intentionally manipulating the intermediate causes in the series (by skillfully utilizing inherent causal power), in order to bring about some desired effect. An obvious example of such a series is a series of dominoes which are carefully lined up, and then set inexorably in motion by an agent who flips the first one.

Another example (and I know this will shock some readers) is Aquinas’ famous hand-stick-stone series. The important point here is not the finite time delay in the propagation of the impulse through the stick from the hand to the stone. Rather, the point is that the particles which comprise the stick each possess an inherent causal power to propagate an impulse, just as it would propagate, slowly but inexorably, through a series of dominoes that were all lined up. The domino example is just the hand-stick-stone case in slow motion, and agency is equally real in both.

To see why, imagine living in a world with somewhat different laws of nature, where the propagation of an impulse from an agent’s hand through his stick to the stone he wanted to hit took (say) one million times longer than it does in our world, so that the end of the stick that was near the stone responded very slowly to the agent’s push at the other end. In such a world, people would continue to use sticks as instruments, but they would simply adapt to the delay.

I conclude, then, that it is somewhat misleading of Feser to single out the members of hierarchical causal series as instrumental causes, when the same description can apply to members of linear causal series, as well.

===================================================================


RETURN TO MAIN MENU

4. Feser’s flawed argument that the First Actualizer must be purely actual

Many of the Church Fathers likened God to the Sun. God, they said, was purely active and in no way passive. Photo courtesy photos-public-domain.com.

What Feser is trying to establish

In chapter 1 of his book, Feser spells out very clearly what he means when he refers to a purely actual Being – namely, one which could not possibly require actualizing in any way whatsoever, as it lacks any kind of potentiality:

Now since what is being explained in this case is the actualization of a thing’s potential for existence, the sort of “first” cause we are talking about here is one which can actualize the potential for others to exist without having to have its own existence actualized by anything.

What this entails is that this cause doesn’t have any potential for existence that needs to be actualized in the first place. It just is actual, always and already actual, as it were. Indeed, you might say that it doesn’t merely have actuality, the way the things it actualizes do, but that it just is pure actuality itself. It doesn’t merely happen not to have a cause of its own, but could not in principle have had or needed one. For being devoid of potentiality, there is nothing in it that could have needed any actualizing, the way other things do. It is in this sense that it is an uncaused cause, or to use Aristotle’s famous expression, an Unmoved Mover. More precisely, we might call it an unactualized actualizer. (2017, p. 27)

Does a First Actualizer need to be purely actual?

Later in the chapter, Feser rebuts a possible criticism, relating to whether his Aristotelian proof for God’s existence actually establishes that the First (or Ultimate) Actualizer is purely actual, or simply a Being which doesn’t need to be actualized from outside, when it actualizes other beings, but which may nonetheless be capable of being actualized (either by itself or by other beings). The point which is at stake here, as Feser realizes, is that unless he can show that the First Actualizer is purely actual, he will be unable to show that it is one, immaterial, eternal, perfect, omnipotent and omniscient. In other words, an Ultimate Actualizer which isn’t purely actual may not turn out to be God:

…[T]he critic might suggest that even if there is a first actualizer, it need not be a purely actual actualizer, one devoid of potentiality. For why not suppose instead that it has potentialities which are simply not in fact being actualized, at least not insofar as it is functioning as the first actualizer in some hierarchical series of causes? Perhaps those actualities are actualized at some other time,when it is not so functioning; or perhaps they never are. But as long as it has them, it will not be a purely actual actualizer, and thus will not have many of the attributes definitive of God – unity, immateriality, eternity, perfection, omnipotence, and so forth.

To see what is wrong with this objection, recall once again that though the argument begins by asking what explains the changes we observe in the world around us, it moves on to the question of what explains the existence, at any moment, of the things that undergo changes. So, the regress of actualizers that we are ultimately concerned with is a regress of the actualizers of the existence of things. The first actualizer in the series is “first”, then, in the sense that it can actualize the existence of other things without its own existence having to be actualized. So, suppose this first actualizer had some potentiality that had to be actualized in order for it to exist. What actualizes that potential? (2017, pp. 66-67)

This is a very poor argument, as it merely shows that the First Actualizer has no potentiality that has to be actualized, in order for it to exist. What Feser fails to show is that this Being doesn’t possess any potentialities whatsoever. It might still have potentialities which it activates when it acts, for instance.

The same criticism applies to Feser’s argument (2017, p. 67) that if the first actualizer had some potentiality that had to be actualized in order for it to exist, it would have either to be actualized from outside (in which case, the Being wouldn’t be the first actualizer) or from within, by (a) some purely actual part of the Being (which will then be the true first actualizer) or (b) some partly actual and partly potential part of the Being (which generates a vicious regress of actualizers). Feser is aiming at a straw man here: the critic of his argument for a purely actual Being is not claiming that the First Actualizer has some potentiality that needs to be actualized in order for it to exist. Rather, all that it is being proposed is the very modest claim that the First Actualizer has some potentialities which it realizes, in some situations, when it acts. Nothing is being asserted about the needs of the First Actualizer, let alone that it needs anything in order to exist, or in order to ground the existence of other things.

Two more arguments for a purely actual Being, by Feser

In chapter 6 of his book, Feser attempts one more time to prove the existence of a purely actual Being:

… [S]uppose we agree that [the First Cause’s] existence involved no actualization of potential. Might we not still say that its activity involved the actualization of potential? Might we not say that while it had no potentialities with respect to its existence, it does have potentialities with respect to its activity (such as its activity of actualizing the existence of other things)? (2017, p. 185)

Here, at last, Feser is finally addressing his critics’ claims, by focusing on the activities of the First Cause of things. Could the First Cause have potentialities with regard to the acts it is capable of performing? Feser disagrees, for two reasons: first, its actions have to reflect its mode of being, which is entirely active; and second, if it had potentialities, it would be a composite Being, and would therefore require an external cause of its own, to hold it together – in which case, it wouldn’t be the First Cause, after all:

There are several problems with this suggestion, however, one of which might be obvious now that we have set out the principle agere sequitur esse, according to which what a thing does reflects what it is. If the first cause of things exists in a purely actual way, how could it act in a less than purely actual way? How could its acting involve potentiality any more than its existence does? A thing’s existence is, after all, what is metaphysically most fundamental about it; everything else follows from that. In this case we are talking about something whose very existence is purely actual and devoid of potentiality. So, from where in its nature are the (metaphysically less fundamental) potentialities for activity that the critic suggests it has supposed to derive?

Another problem with the suggestion in question is that to say of God that he has potentiality with respect to his activity, though not with respect to his existence, entails that God has parts – a purely actual part, and a part that is a potentiality. Now, as we saw in chapter 2, whatever has parts requires a cause. The reason is that the whole of which the parts are constituents is merely potential until actualized by some principle which combines the parts. This principle cannot be something intrinsic to the thing, for in that case it would be the cause of itself, which is incoherent. So, it must be something extrinsic to the thing… Even if the thing had no temporally prior cause, it would still require an ontologically prior cause. (2017, p. 185)

Neither of these arguments is particularly convincing. Feser’s first argument, if correct, would actually prove too much: it would prove that the purely actual Being is incapable of generating potentialities, even in creatures – for where in His purely actual nature do these potentialities spring from? From creatures’ natures, Feser may reply. Fine: Who is the Author of those?

It gets worse. The purely actual Being is also a necessary Being. If the principle that “action follows being” is correct, then such a Being should only be able to perform necessary actions. It would therefore be unable to perform a contingent action, such as creating (and maintaining in existence) our universe, since such an action would not reflect its mode of being.

Feser’s rhetorical question, “If the first cause of things exists in a purely actual way, how could it act in a less than purely actual way?”, also strikes me as bizarre. For how can an action be anything other than actual? An action is an actualization: it can never be less than purely actual. An action realizes a potential, but that does not make the action itself potential.

Finally, I have to say that the Scholastic principle which Feser appeals to, that “action follows being,” is far from self-evident. From the fact that thing’s existence is more fundamental than its actions, it does not follow that a thing’s mode of action reflects its mode of being, as Feser maintains it does.

Patricia Soltysik, taking part in the April 1974 Hiberina bank robbery, in Noriega St., San Francisco, running out of the bank with a bag of money. Public domain image, courtesy of Wikipedia.

The Scholastic principle that “action follows being” is extremely vague, and as we have seen, there are good grounds for doubting that it is true. Can anything be salvaged from this highly suspect principle, then? I suggest that the core of truth underlying the principle is that the actions we attribute to a thing cannot be at variance with the natural category which it belongs to, as a being. For instance, it would make no sense to say that a cloud robbed a bank, for the actions involved in robbing a bank can only be meaningfully ascribed to an animate being capable of talking and moving at will. Does this revised principle rule out a First or Ultimate Actualizer being able to realize its own potentialities, when it acts? I see no grounds for thinking so.

So much, then, for Feser’s first argument for a purely actual Being. What of the second argument?

Feser’s second argument fares no better, as it simply assumes, without any evidence whatsoever, that if a purely actual Being had potentialities, then it would also have parts. But why need this be so? And what is a part, anyway? Surprisingly, Feser nowhere defines the term, in his entire book.

Suppose now that I make a choice, and in doing so, actualize one potentiality which is open to me as a human being: does it then follow that I and the possibility I chose to actualize are two distinct parts of some greater whole, as if I and my choice were somehow two distinct elements? And if my actions are part of this greater whole, what do we call it? We cannot call it “me,” because that’s what I am, and according to Feser, I am distinct from my actions. But if my actions are not part of me, then what are they part of?

Alternatively, let us consider an utterly impersonal actualization of a potentiality: suppose that a radioactive atom decays randomly, and in so doing, actualize one potentiality which is open to it as a radionuclide: namely, to release excess energy by decaying, rather than retaining it. Would anyone wish to argue that the atom and its act of releasing energy are two distinct parts of some greater whole?

To my mind, it sounds downright bizarre to insist that a thing and its actions constitute a “twosome,” which is greater than the thing itself. This strikes me as a very peculiar way of talking, and Feser needs to justify it.

I conclude that Feser’s arguments purporting to show that the Ultimate Actualizer, or First Cause, must be a purely actual Being, contain question-begging assumptions, as well as some very peculiar assumptions about parts, which Feser needs to explain, before he can possibly hope to convince his readers.

Are there any other arguments for a purely actual Being?

Are there any other arguments for a purely actual Being, in Feser’s book? It turns out that there are a few, very brief arguments, embedded in Feser’s second, third, fourth and fifth proofs. Let us examine each of these in turn.

(a) The Neo-Platonic proof

In chapter two, which argues for the existence of an absolutely simple Being, Feser attempts to show that such a Being would have to be purely actual:

The One also has to be regarded as purely actual rather than a mixture of actuality and potentiality. obviously it has to be at least partially actual, for the reasons set out in the previous chapter – namely, that nothing that is merely potential can do anything, and the One is doing something insofar as it is the cause of all things other than itself. But if it was less than purely actual, then it would be partially potential. In that case it would have parts – an actual part and a potential part – and it has no parts. So, again, it must be purely actual. (2017, p. 76)

Once again, Feser appeals to the hidden premise (for which he supplies no argument) that any being which isn’t purely actual has parts. This assumption makes sense, only if we are talking about something whose existence isn’t fully actual: such a being would indeed have actual and potential elements. However, Feser fails to show why an Actualizer whose existence doesn’t require actualization would still need to have parts, in order to realize some potentiality when acting.

(b) The Augustinian proof

In the third chapter of his book, where Feser argues for the existence of a Mind which contains all concepts and exists of necessity, Feser tries to establish that this Mind would have to be purely actual:

Consider that an intellect that existed of absolute necessity would have to be purely actual. For suppose its existence presupposes the actualization of some potential. In that case its existence would be contingent on such an actualization, in which case it wouldn’t exist of absolute necessity. (2017, p. 106)

The foregoing argument merely shows that the Mind that exists of absolute necessity is purely actual in its Being. However, nothing follows from this fact, with regard to the activities of such a Mind. As far as I can tell, Feser has given us no reason to suppose that it is incapable of actualizing potentials, when it makes choices.

(c) The Thomistic proof

In his discussion of the Thomistic proof for God’s existence in chapter four, Feser explains why a Being which is Pure Existence could not be anything less than purely actual:

As Aquinas emphasized, in a thing whose essence is distinct from its existence, its essence and existence are related as potentiality and actuality. Fido’s essence, by itself amounts only to a potential thing, not an actual thing. Only when Fido’s essence has existence imparted to it is there an actual thing – namely, Fido. Now if essence considered by itself is a kind of potentiality, and existence considered by itself is a kind of actuality, then that which just is existence, that which just is subsistent existence itself rather than merely one derivatively existing thing alongside others, must be purely actual. It could not have some potentiality for existence that needs to be actualized, for then it would not be something which just is existence, but rather merely yet some other thing to which existence must be imparted. (2017, p. 127)

Again, all that Feser has shown here is that a Being which is Pure Existence contains no potentialities within its being. This in no way precludes the possibility that such a Being may be capable of realizing potentialities when it acts.

(d) The Rationalist proof

In chapter five of Feser’s book, where he invokes the Principle of Sufficient Reason to establish the existence of a Necessary Being, Feser argues that this Being must be purely actual:

Why should we think of the necessary being as God? Consider first that, from the fact that it is necessary, it follows that it exists in a purely actual way, rather than by virtue of having potentialities that need to be actualized. For if it had such potentialities, then its existence would be contingent upon the existence of something which actualizes those potentialities – in which case it wouldn’t really exist in a necessary way at all. (2017, p. 159)

Once again, Feser’s argument merely establishes that God is in no way potential, as regards His manner of existence. However, this conclusion tells us nothing whatsoever about His activities.

I conclude that Feser has failed to mount a satisfactory case for the existence of a purely actual Being, as opposed to an Ultimate Actualizer which needs nothing outside it to “hold it together” as a being, and which doesn’t need to be actualized by anything else, either in order to exist, or in order to ground the existence of other beings. That being the case, the arguments Feser puts forward in his Aristotelian proof for God’s unity, eternity, immutability, incorporeality, perfection, omnipotence, goodness and omniscience, all collapse, since they all proceed on the assumption that there is a purely actual Being, who is in no way potential. And since Feser’s other proofs all depend on the arguments put forward in his Aristotelian proof for these divine attributes, it follows that they too are unsound arguments, as they all rest on the same dubious premise that a purely actual Being exists.

===================================================================


RETURN TO MAIN MENU

5. Feser’s flawed argument that there can only be ONE First Actualizer

The Temple of Heaven in Beijing, built in honor of Shangdi, who was regarded as the absolute God of the universe in ancient China.

Feser’s argument for the unity of the First Actualizer is, as we will see, marred by two gaping holes in his logic: Feser fails to anticipate the possibility that two First Actualizers might not belong to any common natural category, and might therefore be characterized by two completely different sets of perfections, which they both realize in their entirety (making them both perfect, in their own respective ways); and he also ignores the possibility that even if they both belong to the same category, they may differ in characteristics which are neither perfections nor deficiencies, such as color.

Feser’s Aristotelian proof of the unity of the First Actualizer

Feser outlines his argument for the unity of a purely actual Being in his formal statement of the Aristotelian proof of God’s existence:

15. In order for there to be more than one purely actual actualizer, there would have to be some differentiating feature that one such actualizer has that the others lack.

16. But there could be such a differentiating feature only of a purely actual actualizer had some unactualized potential, which, being purely actual, it does not have.

17. So, there can be no such differentiating feature, and thus no way for there to be more than one purely actual actualizer. (2017, p. 36)

Feser sets up his argument for the unity of the First Actualizer by introducing the notion of a privation, and linking it to the related notion of a potential. To have a privation is to fail to realize some potential, and to be perfect is to be without any privations, or deficiencies:

For example, a squirrel which has been hit by a car may be unable to run away from predators as swiftly as it needs to; and a tree whose roots have been damaged may be unstable or unable to take in all the water and nutrients it needs in order to remain healthy. A defect of this sort is (to use some traditional philosophical jargon) a privation, the absence of some feature a thing would naturally require so as to be complete. It involves the failure to realize some potential inherent in a thing. Something is perfect, then, to the extent that it has actualized such potentials and is without privations. But then a purely actual cause of things, precisely since it is purely actual and thus devoid of unrealized potentiality or privation, possesses maximal perfection. (2017, p. 30)

Two points are worth making here. First, while having a privation entails having an unrealized potentiality, it does not follow that being perfect and having no privations entails having no unrealized potentialities. Thus a perfect being could still have potentialities which it does not realize. What a perfect being cannot have are potentialities which it should realize but is unable to.

Second, Feser’s definition of maximal perfection is extremely modest: it would imply that an entity which is capable of doing only one thing, which is does very well, is maximally perfect! In my previous post, I discussed Alvin Plantinga’s hypothetical example of McEar, who has the essential property of only having the power to scratch his ear, and who is incapable of doing anything else. On Feser’s definition, McEar would qualify as a maximally perfect being. So, too, would a hypothetical entity called McEye, which is capable only of seeing what’s in front of it. That should tell us that something is very wrong with Feser’s definition of maximal perfection.

Feser then appeals to the notions of a privation and of maximal perfection, in order to explain why there can only be one purely actual Cause of things:

Could there be more than one such cause? There could not, not even in principle. For there can be two or more of a kind only if there is something to differentiate them, something that one instance has that the others lack… More generally, two or more things of a kind are to be differentiated in terms of some perfection or privation that one has and the other lacks… But as we have seen, what is purely actual is completely devoid of any privation and is maximal in perfection. Hence, there can be no way in principle to differentiate one purely actual cause from another in terms of their respective perfections or privations. But then such a cause possesses the attribute of unity – that is to say, there cannot be, even in principle, more than one purely actual cause. hence it is one and the same unactualized actualizer to which all things owe their existence. (2017, p. 30)

Later, in chapter 6, Feser elaborates his point, by appealing to Aristotle’s account of how two things of a kind can be said to differ:

… God is purely actual, with no potentiality at all. And this entails his unity, because there cannot, even in principle, be more than one thing which is pure actuality. The reason is that for there to be more than one thing of a certain kind, there must be a distinction between the thing and the species of which it is a member, or (if the thing in question is a species) between the species and the genus of which it is a member. And there can be no such distinction without there also being a distinction between the thing’s potentialities and its actualities. (2017, p. 186)

Two gaping holes in Feser’s logic

European wild horse phenotypes. Image courtesy of DFoidl and Wikipedia.

We can now see the gaping holes in Feser’s argument for the unity of the Purely Actual Actualizer. First, Feser assumes, without justification, that if there were two purely actual beings, they would be two of a kind. That would make sense only if “being actual” defined some natural kind, like “being a horse.” However, there is no reason to think that it does. There may not be any common term (like horsiness) which can be predicated univocally of two purely actual beings; the resemblance between them may be purely analogical. Feser should be aware of this possibility: in his book, he carefully distinguishes between terms like “animal,” which are predicated of all species in exactly the same way (univocally), and terms like “being,” which are predicated analogically of different entities (2017, pp. 178-179). Why, then, couldn’t “First Actualizer” be an analogical term, rather than a univocal one?

Second, there is an illicit slide in Feser’s argument, from one meaning of lack to another. When Feser writes that there can be two or more of a kind only if there is “something that one instance has that the others lack,” the notion of “lack” he employs is: does not have. Two horses, for instance, may be completely alike in all respects except for their color: one is black, and the other is a chestnut. Blackness is something that the chestnut horse does not have. But it is not something that the chestnut horse should have, so we do not call this lack a defect. Next, Feser appeals to the stronger premise that “two or more things of a kind are to be differentiated in terms of some perfection or privation that one has and the other lacks.” Here, he is assuming that these things can only differ by virtue of some excellence which one possesses and which the other fails to realize. Finally, Feser argues that a purely actual being is free of all imperfections, in order to establish that it is unique.

In short: what Feser overlooks are: (i) the possibility that two purely actual beings might not share a list of common perfections which they are both supposed to possess, but might instead possess two completely different sets of perfections which they both realize in their entirety, making them both perfect in fundamentally different ways (think of McEar and McEye); and (ii) even supposing that two purely actual beings share such a list of perfections, there remains the possibility that they may differ in features which are neither perfections nor deficiencies, like the color of a horse.

I conclude that Feser’s argument for the unity of a purely actual Being is a badly flawed one, which trades on ambiguity and contains a number of unexamined premises.

Unfortunately, Feser’s faulty argument for the unity of a purely actual Being doesn’t just invalidate his first (Aristotelian) proof of God’s existence; it invalidates two of his other proofs, as well, as the following excerpts from the Augustinian and Rationalist proofs reveal:

(a) The Augustinian proof

19. A necessarily existing intellect would be purely actual.

20. There cannot be more than one thing that is purely actual.

21. So, there cannot be more than one necessarily existing intellect. (2017, p. 110)

(b) The Rationalist proof

19. A necessary being would have to be purely actual, absolutely simple or noncomposite, and something which just is subsistent existence itself.

20. But there can in principle be only one thing which is purely actual, absolutely simple or noncomposite, and something which just is subsistent existence itself. (2017, p. 163)

By relying too heavily on the Aristotelian argument as the backbone of his proofs of God’s existence, Feser has done himself a disservice, since any defect in any portion of the Aristotelian argument which is borrowed by the other proofs will render those arguments faulty, as well.

To sum up: Feser’s first, Aristotelian argument for God’s existence is flawed at its very roots. It fails to establish the existence of a purely actual Being, and it fails to prove that there is only one such Being. Since Feser’s arguments for the remaining Divine attributes are built on the foundation of these two attributes, I conclude that the Aristotelian argument is utterly useless, as a proof of God’s existence.

===================================================================

C. FLAWS WHICH UNDERCUT FESER’S SECOND PROOF

Summary of my argument: I now turn to Feser’s second, neo-Platonic argument for God’s existence, which endeavors to establish the existence of one (and only one) absolutely simple Being, which is utterly devoid of parts. Unfortunately, nowhere in his entire book does Feser provide a definition of “part”: a startling omission. After examining various passages in Feser’s writings, I put forward a definition which I believe captures Feser’s metaphysical insights as to what what a part is, judging from scattered passages in his writings. Unfortunately for Feser’s argument, the definition I provide shows only that an absolutely simple Being cannot be composed of any elements which are ontologically prior to it. Nothing in the “Feserian” definition which I propose precludes such a Being from having either properties (which flow from its essence and are ontologically posterior to it), or intrinsic accidents (such as a horse’s color, which does not flow from its essence, but which it has to have anyway). Feser, however, upholds a very radical view of Divine simplicity: not only does he hold God’s nature to be simple (as most Christians do), but as a Thomist, he also holds that God has no properties or real accidents of any kind. Additionally, Feser’s argument that there can only be one absolutely simple Being suffers from the same deficiencies as his Aristotelian argument that there can only be one purely actual Being. Feser assumes, without justification, that if there were two absolutely simple beings, they would both be members of some common category (i.e. a species or a genus); and he also assumes (without explaining why) that the additional features which distinguish any two members of this common category would have to be parts of those entities. I conclude that these holes in Feser’s logic, coupled with his failure to provide a proper definition of “part,” vitiate his second, neo-Platonic argument for God’s existence.


RETURN TO MAIN MENU

6. Bad Mereology: Feser’s failure to define what it means for something to be a part of a whole

Various electronic components. Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

Feser writes quite a lot on the subject of whether God has parts. Curiously, however, nowhere in his entire book, or in any of his other books on metaphysics, does Feser tell us what he actually means by one – a startling omission. The question is important, because the term “part” is variously defined by different authors.

Some authors define the parts of an object in terms of their separability. Thus if A and B were inseparable from one another, these authors would deny that they were distinct parts of anything greater. Feser rejects this view, however: in his Scholastic Metaphysics (editiones scholasticae, 2014, p. 247), he declares that Thomists reject the assumption (made by Scotists and Suarezians) “that a real distinction entails separability,” and he uses the example of the essence and the existence of a thing to illustrates his point: neither can exist apart from the other, yet (Thomists insist) there is a real distinction between the two. In his latest work, Five Proofs of the Existence of God, Feser argues vigorously for the view that a thing’s essence and existence possess incompatible attributes, which make them really distinct from one another (rather than just logically distinct). Another example Feser gives (borrowed from the philosopher David Oderberg) is that of the circumference and radius of a circle: neither is separable from the other, yet there is a real distinction between the two (2017, pp. 123-124).

Other authors define the parts of an object in terms of their inter-connections: parts must be designed to work as a coherent entity, or otherwise they are not really one thing. Feser is sympathetic to this view, for in a blog post titled, Nature versus Art (April 30, 2011), he contrasts natural objects (such as a liana vine) with artifacts (such as a hammock): in the former case, the parts “have an inherent tendency to function together to allow the liana to exhibit the growth patterns it does, to take in water and nutrients, and so forth,” whereas in the latter case, “the parts of the hammock … have no inherent tendency to function together as a hammock”: the function they perform is “extrinsic or imposed from outside.” Accordingly, “[a] liana vine is a true substance,” or thing, whereas “[t]he hammock is not a true substance.”

Other writers define the parts of an object in terms of their being in some way prior to the whole they comprise: the whole is said to be made out of such parts. Feser appears to favor such a view: in his discussion of Divine simplicity, he argues that even if a thing made up of parts were eternal, it would still require a cause, to keep its parts together: “Even if the thing had no temporally prior cause, it would still require an ontologically prior cause” (2017, p. 185). Here, Feser is clearly assuming that parts are ontologically prior to the whole which they comprise.

So how would Feser define the parts of an object? I would like to propose the following definition, distilled from his writings on the subject:

A and B are two parts of a compound C, if and only if:

(i) they are ontologically prior to C;
(ii) they possess incompatible attributes, which make them really distinct;
(iii) they have an inherent tendency to function together; and
(iv) the reality they comprise is greater than either of them, when considered on its own (wholes being greater than their parts).

A puzzling inconsistency

On such a definition, it is easy to see why Feser would regard matter and form (or for that matter, essence and existence) as two parts of the thing they comprise. However, the definition I have proposed would seem to preclude a thing’s properties from being parts of that thing, as parts are supposed to be ontologically prior to the whole they comprise, whereas properties are said to “flow” or follow from a thing’s essence, as the capacity to find things amusing follows from someone’s being a rational animal (2017, p. 193). And indeed, it would be very odd to speak of water’s liquidity as being a part of it, or a human being’s ability to laugh as being a part of them. However, Feser does just that: he declares that “the essence of a thing, its properties, and its intrinsic accidents (contingent and otherwise) … are concrete, intrinsic constituents of the thing itself” (2017, p. 193), and he adds: “For example, Socrates’ rational animality is a constituent of Socrates himself, as is his property of being capable of finding things amusing, and his contingent accident of having a certain skin color” (2017, p. 193).

It turns out that the God Whose existence Feser is trying to demonstrate is absolutely simple in a very radical sense of the term. Feser is not just saying that God has a simple and indivisible nature; rather, he is insisting that God has no properties which are distinct from His nature, even if they follow from this nature (2017, p. 194), and that God has no contingent real accidents, which actualize Him in any additional sense, as a Creator (2017, p. 196). As we’ll see below, making these assertions, Feser is going beyond what the traditional creeds and councils of Christendom have defined: Christians have traditionally held that God’s nature is simple, and refrained from speculating about His properties or accidents.

Thus there appears to be a genuine inconsistency in Feser’s mereology. Either the parts of a thing have to be ontologically prior to the whole they comprise, or they don’t. If they do, then the properties and intrinsic accidents of a thing are not parts of it, which means that there is no good reason for Feser to insist that God has no (real) accidents. However, in his book (2017, pp. 195-196), Feser goes to considerable lengths to rebut philosopher Thomas V. Morris’s contention that “God has both necessary (essential) and contingent properties,” by denying that God has any contingent real properties and affirming that God’s necessary real properties are in fact identical to the Divine essence. What’s more, he adds that for someone to maintain that God is a mixture of potency and act, or essence and existence, or “in any other way composite,” is tantamount to affirming atheism (2017, p. 195). This is a tall claim indeed: can Feser justify it?

===================================================================


RETURN TO MAIN MENU

7. Feser’s flawed arguments for the existence of an Absolutely Simple Being

Marble bust, believed to be of the Neo-Platonic philosopher Plotinus (c. 205 – 270). Plotinus originated the idea that God is absolutely simple. Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

Feser’s argument for the existence of an absolutely simple Being can be found in chapter two of his book, in which he presents the Neo-Platonist philosopher Plotinus’ proof of God’s existence, and also in chapter six, where he addresses and rebuts several objections to the doctrine of Divine simplicity. Accordingly, it is these chapters which I have decided to focus on first.

Curiously, Feser says almost nothing about the Divine attribute of simplicity in his Aristotelian proof of the existence of God. There is no mention of it, for instance, in his formal statement of the proof (2017, pp. 35-37), and he only briefly touches on the issue in the final section of chapter one (“Why an unmovable mover?”, 2017, pp. 66-68). Additionally, there is a single sentence in Feser’s Rationalist proof for God’s existence (2017, pp. 159-160) where he explains why a necessary Being has to be simple. As these arguments are very brief, I will defer my evaluation of them until a later point in this section.

Feser’s Neo-Platonic proof of the existence of an absolutely simple Being

Baron Munchausen pulls himself out of a mire by his own hair. Image courtesy of Oskar Herrfurth and Wikipedia.

The Neo-Platonic proof, which originated with the philosopher Plotinus (c. 205-270) seeks to establish the existence of an absolutely simple Being, before going on to deduce other attributes of this Being which, Feser maintains, warrant it being called “God.” Before setting forth his proof of the existence of an absolutely simple Being, Feser argues that since the parts of a thing are ontologically (if not temporally) prior to the whole, the existence of these parts cannot be explained by the whole that they comprise, for then we would have a vicious circle, with the parts explaining the whole and the whole explaining the parts:

[A] composite depends on its parts not merely … in a temporal sense, but more fundamentally (and always) in an atemporal sense. At any particular moment, a composite thing’s existence will presuppose that its parts exist and are put together in the right way at that moment, and this will be the case whether or not that composite thing has existed always, or only a certain number of minutes, hours, days, or years, or only for an instant.

How do the parts of a composite come together to form the whole? It can’t be the composite itself that causes this to happen... Chairs, for example, don’t assemble themselves… But again, even if we think atemporally of the chair at any particular moment, the existence of the whole depends on the existence and proper arrangement of the parts. And the chair as a whole can’t be the cause of those parts existing, and being assembled in just the right way, at the moment. We would in that case have an explanatory vicious circle, insofar as the existence of the whole would depend on the existence and arrangement of the parts, and the existence and arrangement of the parts would depend on the existence of the whole. The chair would be lifting itself up by its own metaphysical bootstraps, as it were. (2017, pp. 70-71)

Having argued that the unity of a whole requires a cause of some sort, Feser endeavors to show that the Ultimate Cause for the parts of a composite thing holding together must be some being (or beings) which is absolutely simple. He does so by arguing that the causal series must be a hierarchical one, as whatever capacity one composite thing may have to hold another composite being together is conditional upon its being held together, which means that its power is purely derivative (unlike the members of a linear causal series, which possess power in their own right). But a hierarchical causal series (unlike a linear one) must have an uncaused first member – in this case, one which is able to hold a thing together without needing anything else to hold it together. Such a being must be utterly simple, asserts Feser:

Now, if some composite thing is caused by another composite thing and that by yet another in a hierarchical causal series, then for the reasons set out in the previous chapter, that series must have a first member. But the first member cannot itself be composite, for then it would require a cause of its own and not be first. So, it must be something noncomposite, something utterly simple in the sense of having no parts of any kind – no material parts, and no metaphysical parts like form and matter or essence and existence.

For any of the composite things of our existence to exist at all here and now, then, there must also exist here and now a noncomposite or utterly simple cause of their existence – a cause which, following the Neo-Platonic philosopher Plotinus, we might call the One. (2017, p. 74)

Q.E.D.? Not quite. As Feser freely acknowledges, the foregoing argument assumes that composite entities need to be held together by something outside them. But why not assume instead that these entities are held together from within? Feser has anticipated this objection, and has a ready reply.

Why couldn’t the parts of a thing have an internal cause for their holding together?

The structure of a sodium chloride crystal. Image courtesy of Wikipedia. Feser maintains that a crystal like this one cannot be held together from within: it requires an external cause (God) to keep its parts together.

Feser now considers two ways in which the parts of a thing might be held together internally, without the need for any external cause to unify the thing. First, a thing containing two parts, A and B, might have some additional part (call it C) which unifies them. Or maybe it’s just a brute fact about the thing that it is made up of parts A and B. Neither suggestion will do, argues Feser:

…[T]he argument assumes that for a composite thing to exist, its parts have to be unified by some external cause. But why assume this? Why not suppose instead that it is precisely some part of a composite thing that unifies its parts, rather than something external? Or why not suppose that the fact that a composite thing’s parts are unified is just an irreducible fact about it?

But as Vallicella has argued, neither of these suggestions really makes any sense. Start with the suggestion that the parts of a thing are unified by some further part. For instance, consider a thing composed of parts A and B. What makes it the case that parts A and B are united in such a way that the composite thing in question exists? The suggestion at hand is that there is some further part, C, which accounts for A and B being united. But the problem is that this just pushes the problem back a stage, since we now need to ask what unites C together with A and B…

Suppose instead that we opt for the alternative suggestion, to the effect that a composite thing’s parts A and B being unified in such a way that it exists is just an irreducible fact about the thing. What exactly does this claim amount to? Does it mean that the thing made up of A and B is itself the cause of A and B being united in such a way that the composite thing exists? That would entail that the composite thing is both the cause of its parts A and B being unified and the effect of its parts A and B being unified – which is incoherent. As we saw above, nothing can be the cause of itself, lifting itself up by its own metaphysical bootstraps. (2017, pp. 83-84)

The problem with Feser’s logic in the foregoing passages is that the two suggestions put forward by Vallicella, as to how A’s being joined to B can be explained from within, do not exhaust the possibilities as to why A happens to be joined to B. Supposing that there is no external cause for A’s being united to B, there may be an internal cause, or there may be no cause at all (i.e. A’s being joined to B is just a brute fact). If the cause is internal, it may be either A itself, or B, or some other part C, or some combination of the above. Vallicella refutes only the third possibility. The first is unintelligible, since by definition, A cannot cause A. (A cause and its effect are necessarily distinct.) That still leaves us with the possibility that A’s being joined to B is caused either by B itself, or by B and some other part(s). Neither of these possibilities is explored by Feser.

Consider, for instance, a sodium chloride crystal (pictured above). We might ask why the sodium ions happen to be joined to the chloride ions. It makes perfect sense to say that the chloride ions themselves bring about the sodium ions being joined to them, while the sodium ions bring about the chloride ions being joined to them. Nor is there any circularity in the explanation proposed here. It would be circular if we supposed that the sodium ions caused the existence of the chloride ions, and that the chloride ions caused the existence of the sodium ions. But that is not what we are supposing here. We are supposing (for argument’s sake) that neither the sodium ions nor the chloride ions have any cause for their existence, but that each causes the other to be attracted to it. This mutual attraction makes perfect sense, because A’s being attracted to B does not presuppose B’s being attracted to A, and vice versa: they are distinct states of affairs, and we can conceive of one being true without the other being true.

Note that in the explanation proposed here, there was no need for us to invoke an additional component, C, to unify A and B. Hence the question posed by Feser, as to what unites C together with A and B, does not arise. Nor did we need to postulate that it was just a brute fact about the composite that A and B happen to be joined together. Rather, all we supposed was that A is naturally attracted to B, and that B is naturally attracted to A. Why should these facts require any further explanation, other than A’s and B’s natures being what they are? If Feser still wants to ask, “Why are A and B that way?”, then the only answer that needs to be given is that if they weren’t that way, then they wouldn’t be A and B anymore: if sodium ions weren’t attracted to chloride ions, then they wouldn’t be sodium ions. And what, we might ask, is wrong with an explanation like that?

Feser’s treatment of Divine simplicity in chapter six

After having presented his five proofs for God’s existence, Feser resumes his discussion of the Divine simplicity in chapter six, where he appears to put forward a new argument as to why the unity of a composite thing cannot have an internal explanation: namely, that the parts of the composite are ontologically (if not temporally) prior to the composite which they form. As far as I can make out, Feser’s argument seems to be that since the parts are prior to the whole, each part is capable of existing without the other part(s). Hence each part requires something else in order to actualize (or bring about) the state of affairs of its being joined to the other part(s):

Now, as we saw in chapter 2, whatever has parts requires a cause. The reason is that the whole of which the parts are constituents is merely potential until actualized by some principle which combines the parts. This principle cannot be something intrinsic to the thing, for in that case it would be the cause of itself, which is incoherent. So, it must be something extrinsic to the thing… Even if the thing had no temporally prior cause, it would still require an ontologically prior cause. (2017, p. 185)

However, from the fact that each part requires something else in order to explain its being joined to the other part(s), it does not follow that the composite as a whole requires something else in order to explain the fact that its parts are joined together. One could say that part A requires B in order to bring about its being joined to B, while part B requires A in order to bring about its being joined to A, but that the whole requires nothing else but A and B in order to explain the union of its parts.

Feser’s reply: because composites can break up, they are not self-explanatory

Seawater in the Strait of Malacca. Image courtesy of Jyi1693 and Wikipedia.

If I were to imagine how Feser might reply at this point, I might suppose that he would object that there is something I am overlooking. For even if the parts of a whole could explain how it manages to hold together, they are still unable to explain the fact that it is together in the first place. And even if one were to answer that the parts have always been together, we can still meaningfully ask why. In the example we discussed above, nothing in the nature of part A entails the proximity of part B: that is an additional fact which requires further explanation. Moreover, composites can and do sometimes break up or decompose: salt crystals, for instance, readily dissolve in water, and most of our planet is covered in saltwater. For any composite of A and B, we can always meaningfully ask why it hasn’t already broken up. And any answer we give will have to appeal to some external states of affairs.

We are forced to conclude, then, that composites whose parts are able to be separated from one another require an external cause for their parts holding together. This appears to be what Feser is driving at in his (very brief) Rationalist argument for the simplicity of the Necessary Being:

[A] necessary being cannot be composed of parts of any kind, for if it were, then its existence would be contingent upon something combining its parts, in which case, again, it wouldn’t really be necessary after all. (2017, p. 160)

The basic idea here is that a composite which is made up of parts which are ontologically prior to the whole they comprise is a being which is able not to be (as the parts might separate in the future) or more generally, able not to have been (as the parts might never have been in proximity to one another, enabling the composite to exist in the first place). The whole, then has a potential for non-existence: the fact of its existence is not a self-explanatory one. And for the existence of such a being, it is reasonable to demand an explanation. That explanation can only be an external cause.

Two possibilities overlooked by Feser

Thus far, Feser appears to be on strong ground, ontologically speaking, but there are two possibilities which he has neglected to consider. The first is admittedly obscure, while the second is readily conceivable.

(a) What about a composite whose parts are inseparable from one another?

The quark structure of the proton. Image courtesy of Jacek rybak and Wikipedia.

The first possibility relates to the possibility of a being whose parts are by nature inseparable from one another. It is certainly difficult to conceive of such a being, but we might think of the quarks which make up a proton (or a neutron), which are always found in association with one another, and which can never be separated from one another. Attempts to separate them by inputting energy only creates new quarks (a quark-antiquark pair), rather than separating the quarks. Still, it might be objected that protons and neutrons are not indestructible, as they can be annihilated by antimatter. Feser might also object that while the separation of the quarks in a proton is physically impossible, it may still be metaphysically possible.

Another (theological) example which might be adduced is that of the persons of the Trinity, Who are by nature inseparable from one another. However, orthodox Christian believers have always denied that the Three Persons of the Trinity are parts of the Godhead. The reason, as far as I can tell, is twofold: first, the Three Persons are not ontologically prior to the Godhead; and second, none of them is less than the Godhead. The second reason only makes sense insofar as the existence of one Person necessarily implies the existence of the other Persons, which is just another way of saying that they are inseparable. However, the first reason is more significant: God is tripersonal because He is God, and because it is God’s nature to be that way. In other words, the reason why the Three Persons are not parts is that the Divine Nature is ontologically prior to the Three Persons. [Actually, there is a legitimate question as to whether the Divine Nature is ontologically prior to the Person of the Father, but that’s a question for another day.]

Speaking of ontological priority, it seems that we finally have an answer to the difficulty we raised. Feser could reply that since (by the definition of “part” which we proposed in section 6 above) the parts which make up a whole are ontologically prior to it, they cannot be both (a) metaphysically inseparable from one another and (b) sufficient by themselves to guarantee the continued existence of the whole they comprise. Even if the quarks making up a proton are metaphysically inseparable, they fail condition (b), as protons can be annihilated. Feser might then add that if the inseparable parts which make up a whole are unable to guarantee its continued existence, then it still makes sense to conclude that there must be an external cause of the existence of the whole.

(b) Turning the tables on Feser: What about a simple Being with multiple properties and/or real contingent accidents?

The phrase “turn the tables” originally came from the game of backgammon. Image courtesy of Tal and Wikipedia.

Up to this point, Feser’s position appear to be a philosophically defensible one. I have, of course, been putting words into his mouth, but it is certainly reasonable to interpret his thinking along the lines I have described above. The situation changes completely, however, when we consider the possibility that a simple Being might nonetheless have multiple properties (which follow from its nature, as our ability to be amused follows from nature as rational animals) and/or real contingent accidents (which do not follow from its nature, but the possession of one of which may be required by its nature – e.g. as a horse has to have a color, even if its nature does not dictate which one – in which case we say that the accident is intrinsic, as well as being real and contingent).

What is noteworthy here is that neither properties nor real contingent accidents (whether intrinsic or otherwise) would qualify as parts, on the definition proposed in section 6 above. For the first condition which a part needs to satisfy is that it is ontologically prior to the whole which it belongs to. Properties do not satisfy this condition because they follow from the nature of the whole, while real contingent accidents are ontologically posterior to the nature of the whole, simply by virtue of being accidents. (A substance is ontologically prior to its accidents.)

That being the case, Feser has no grounds for arguing against the possibility of a Being Whose nature is simple, but which has multiple properties and/or multiple real contingent accidents. Since such a Being would still not be a purely actual Being (because its nature possesses the potential to realize these properties and/or real contingent accidents), and since, as we saw above, Feser’s entire argument that an immutable, eternal, immaterial, incorporeal, perfect, omnipotent, fully good, intelligent, and omniscient Being exists, Whom we would call “God”, depends on the vital assumption that there is a purely actual Being, it follows that unless Feser can rule out the very possibility of a Being with multiple properties and/or real contingent accidents, His case for God fails.

With regard to the properties which follow from a being’s nature, Feser objects that if a being were to have such properties, they would still require an external cause: as he puts it, “whatever is composite or nonsimple is causally dependent on something else and thus cannot be the First Cause” (2017, p. 194). Thus, “if God’s wisdom and power (say) were distinct, then there would have to be some cause which combines them so that God exists” (2017, p. 194).

Properties are not parts

By now, we should be able to see what is wrong with Feser’s reply. What it assumes is that a being with multiple properties would be a composite being, having parts. But as we have seen, it cannot be said to have parts merely by virtue of having properties, as parts are ontologically prior to the whole they comprise, whereas properties are ontologically posterior to it, as they follow from the nature of the thing they inhere in. Feser might still want to object that a thing’s nature plus its properties is “greater than” the thing itself, and that a cause is needed to account for the unity of the two. But if an external cause were needed, then the properties would no longer be properties, since by definition, a thing’s properties (as Scholastic philosophers use that term) follow from its very essence (2017, p. 193), and therefore require no external cause to bring them into existence.

I conclude that we cannot rule out the possibility of a simple being, with no parts, possessing multiple properties. However, such a being, if it existed, would not be a purely actual Being, so Feser’s arguments for the Divine attributes would not apply to such a being: it may or may not possess them.

Can a being with a simple nature have contingent real accidents?

What about the possibility of a simple being, with no parts, having multiple contingent real accidents? Once again, since these accidents are ontologically posterior to the being’s nature, they cannot be called parts, and hence we cannot automatically conclude that they require an external cause to account for the being’s possessing them. Of course, many of the contingent real accidents of a thing (be it an animal, vegetable or mineral) do turn out to have external causes: my point here is that they need not, in all cases.

One possible case in which contingent real accidents have no external cause relates to accidents which an entity may possess at random. (For example, particles at the quantum level may possess contingent real accidents which are randomly generated.) Another, more persuasive illustration of contingent real accidents having no external cause relates to free choice. When an agent makes a choice (e.g. to become an author), he actualizes [or realizes] himself in a way in which he would not be so actualized, were he to make a different choice or no choice at all. This remains the case, even if the agent’s choice is a timeless one: a choice (whether timeless or time-bound) is a contingent actualization of the agent making it. And being free, it requires no external cause.

Morris’ objection to the classical definition of Divine simplicity

This brings me to Thomas V. Morris’ criticism of the doctrine of Divine simplicity, which Feser discusses in his book (2017, pp. 195-196). [By the way, I haven’t discussed Plantinga’s objections to the doctrine, as Feser makes a a very convincing case (2017, pp. 191-195) that Plantinga’s criticisms are fundamentally misinformed.] Morris objects that some things are necessarily true of God (e.g. His being omnipotent), while others are true only contingently – for example, God’s being the Creator of the world, which He need not have made. Morris argues that “there seems to be no other way to capture this truth than to say that God has both necessary (essential) and contingent properties” (quoted in Feser, 2017, p. 195). From a Scholastic standpoint, Morris’ terminology is a little inaccurate – as, for instance, when he refers to God’s having contingent properties rather than contingent accidents – but that in no way undermines the point he is making, which is that a contingent accident is nonetheless real, and if it is a choice, it is a real actualization of an agent (albeit a contingent one). God’s being, on the other hand, is wholly necessary. It would be a flat-out contradiction to equate a contingent actualization of God (when He makes a choice) with the necessary actualization of God’s nature. Consequently, if God exists, then God cannot be absolutely simple, in the manner stipulated by Feser – i.e. devoid of all potentialities. (I might add, in passing, that Catholic doctrine has not defined God’s simplicity in Feser’s strong, Aristotelian sense. The Fourth Lateran Council of 1215 defined only that God has one essence, substance, or nature absolutely simple, saying nothing about the possibility of God having accidents in addition to His simple essence.)

The motto “Fiat Lux” (Let there be light) on the Salther Gate at the University of California, Berkeley. Image courtesy of Shea and Wikipedia.

So how does Feser respond to Morris’ objection? Drawing upon a distinction formulated by the philosopher Peter Geach, he denies the reality of God’s contingent properties (or rather, accidents), and argues that they are instead purely relational properties (which Geach referred to as “Cambridge properties”), which exist only in the creatures God made, and not in God Himself. But this seems absurd. By definition, a choice is an actualization which occurs within the mind of the agent: thus when God said, “Let there be light,” that was a (timeless) actualization of His Mind. Feser seems to be confusing God’s free choices (which are contingent actualizations of God Himself) with their effects (which relate to creatures). Thus for Feser to assert that God “has no contingent real properties” is simply absurd.

A short note on Feser’s Aristotelian argument for the simplicity of the First Actualizer

Feser presents a very short Aristotelian argument for the simplicity of the First Actualizer, near the very end of chapter one (in response to the objection, Why an unmovable mover?):

Should we say … that the first actualizer has some purely actual part that actualizes the part that is merely potential? But in that case, it will be this purely actual part that is the true first actualizer, and the potential “part” will not really be a part of the first actualizer, but merely the first of its effects. (2017, p. 67)

Feser presents brief Aristotelian argument in a similar vein, in chapter six:

If there were in God a distinction between potentiality and actuality, or his essence and existence, or any other parts at all, then he would, like everything else, require a cause of his own… (Into the bargain, allowing that there could be some composite thing which lacked a cause would also undermine the very arguments that led us to God in the first place.) (2017, p. 189)

The underlying thinking here is that a potentiality is incapable of actualizing itself, and hence requires an external cause to actualize it. But as Feser is well aware, potentialities are of two kinds: active and passive. And there seems to be no inherent reason why an agent with the active potential (or capacity) to make a free choice should require an external cause, in order to do so. That being the case, there is no reason why such a being, if it possessed a simple nature, would require an external cause in order to realize its capacity to make choices.

I conclude that Feser’s case for the existence of an absolutely simple Being, which has no parts, properties or accidents, is a badly flawed one – flawed by a failure to define the word “part” and failure to explain why properties or contingent real accidents require an external cause, as Feser seems to think. That being the case, Feser’s second proof for the existence of God fails.

I shall now examine Feser’s arguments that there can only be one absolutely simple Being.

===================================================================


RETURN TO MAIN MENU

8. Feser’s argument that there can only be ONE Absolutely Simple Being

Having argued in chapter two for the existence of an absolutely simple being or beings, Feser’s next task is to show that there can only be one such being. Feser’s proof employs a reductio ad absurdum: if there were two or more, they would need to be distinguished by some additional feature which one possessed and which the others did not, in which case they would no longer be simple beings, contrary to our original supposition. Here is Feser’s informal statement of the argument:

…[S]uppose there were two or more non-composite or utterly simple causes of things. Then there would have to be some feature the possession of which distinguishes one of them from another. Noncomposite or simple cause A would differ from noncomposite or simple cause B insofar as A has feature F, which B lacks, and B has feature G, which A lacks. But in that case neither A nor B would be really simple or noncomposite after all. A would be a simple or noncomposite cause plus F, and B would be a simple or noncomposite cause plus G. F and G would be different parts, one of which each of these causes has and the other of which it lacks. But a simple or noncomposite cause has no parts. So, there can be no feature one cause has and the other lacks. So, there can be no way one such cause would differ from another, and so there just couldn’t be more than one such cause. (2017, pp. 74-75)

And here is Feser’s formal proof of the unity of an absolutely simple Being:

10. In order for there to be more than absolutely one simple or noncomposite cause, each would have to have some differentiating feature that the others lacked.

11. But for a cause to have such a feature would be for it to have parts, in which case it would not really be simple or noncomposite.

12. So, no absolutely simple or noncomposite cause can have such a differentiating feature.

13. So, there cannot be more than one absolutely simple or noncomposite cause. (2017, p. 80)

Eastern Grey Squirrel in Florida. Image courtesy of Tomfriedel, BirdPhotos.com and Wikipedia.

However, there are two flaws in Feser’s argument. First, Feser assumes, without justification, that if there were two absolutely simple beings, they would be two of a kind. However, Feser provides us with no reason to think that “being absolutely simple” defines some natural kind, like “being a squirrel,” to cite one of his examples. Two absolutely simple beings may be fundamentally different, so that no term can be predicated of both, univocally. The resemblance between the two may be purely analogical (e.g. each is a cause which holds composite beings together).

Second, even supposing that these absolutely simple beings belonged to the same natural kind, Feser assumes that the additional features which distinguish two members of this natural kind would have to be parts. But as we saw above in section 6, Feser insists elsewhere in his book that parts must be “ontologically prior” to the whole which they comprise (2017, p. 185). So if two beings of the same kind were distinguished by some feature F which was ontologically posterior to their common essence, then this extra feature would not qualify as a part, on Feser’s definition, and Feser’s reductio ad absurdum argument would collapse.

I conclude that Feser’s argument that there can only be one absolutely simple Being is flawed by hidden assumptions and bad mereology.

To sum up: In order for Feser’s second proof of God’s existence to work, he would need to have a well-thought theory of what it means for a thing to be part of a whole, and what it means for two things to differ from one another. Sadly, it appears that he has neither: at no stage does he even attempt to define what a part is, and (as we saw above in section 5) his explanation of how two things can differ is borrowed uncritically from Aristotle’s account of how two things of a kind differ. I am forced to conclude that Feser’s second proof, like his first, fails to demonstrate the existence of an absolutely simple Being, or its unity.

===================================================================

D. FLAWS WHICH RUIN ALL OF FESER’S FIVE PROOFS


RETURN TO MAIN MENU

9. Why Feser’s proofs that the First Actualizer must be immutable, eternal, immaterial, incorporeal, perfect, good, omnipotent and omniscient all fail

A house of cards. Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

Since Feser’s arguments attempting to deduce the attributes of God are all based on the faulty premise (whose flaws were exposed in section 4 above) that there is a purely actual Being, it follows that Feser’s arguments for the Divine attributes collapse like a house of cards.

It should be borne in mind that all of Feser’s proofs rely on these Aristotelian arguments, in order to deduce the existence of an immutable, eternal, immaterial, incorporeal, perfect, omnipotent, fully good, intelligent, and omniscient Being – in other words, a Being whom we would call “God.” If these arguments are flawed, then all of Feser’s arguments for the existence of God are equally flawed.

The following excerpts, which are taken from Feser’s formal statement of his Aristotelian proof in chapter one, will serve to illustrate my point.

Feser’s arguments for God’s immutability, eternity, immateriality and incorporeality all take as their starting point the existence of a Being Who is purely actual, and devoid of all potentiality. If such a being existed, it would be unchangeable, timeless (i.e. eternal) and hence immaterial and incorporeal.

Immutability

19. In order for this purely actual actualizer to be capable of change, it would have to have potentials capable of actualization.

20. But, being purely actual, it lacks any such potentials.

21. So, it is immutable or incapable of change. (2017, p. 35)

Eternity

22. If this purely actual actualizer existed in time, then it would be capable of change, which it is not.

23. So, this purely actual actualizer is eternal, existing outside of time. (2017, p. 35)

Immateriality

24. If this purely actual actualizer were material, then it would be changeable and exist in time, which it does not.

25. So, this purely actual actualizer is immaterial. (2017, p. 35)

Incorporeality

26. If the purely actual actualizer were corporeal, then it would be material, which it is not.

27. So, the purely actual actualizer is incorporeal. (2017, p. 35)

Feser’s argument for the perfection of the Purely Actual Actualizer employs a definition of evil as the lack of some actualization which should be present – which would make no sense unless it could be present, which in turn implies the existence of a potential in that being. I’d like to make two brief observations at this point. First, if there exists an irredeemably evil being (say, the Devil) then by definition, such a being has no potential to improve; hence the presence of an unactualized potential in a being does not necessarily follow from its being evil. Second, the mere absence of imperfections in a being does not automatically render it perfect. It would sound odd, for instance, to describe an electron as a perfect specimen of its kind. “Normal” might be a better word.

Perfection

28. If the purely actual actualizer were imperfect is any way, it would have some unactualized potential, which, being purely actual, it does not have.

29. So, the purely actual actualizer is perfect. (2017, p. 35)

Feser’s argument for the goodness of the Purely Actual Actualizer uses a very weak definition of maximal goodness: a thing is fully good if it lacks nothing. The problem with this definition is that a perfect specimen of any creature (e.g. a prize sheep) would satisfy the same criterion. All that really follows from Feser’s argument is that a purely actual Being, if it existed,would have no abnormalities.

Goodness

30. For something to be less than fully good is for it to have a privation – that is, to fail to actualize some feature proper to it.

31. A purely actual actualizer, being purely actual, can have no such privation.

32. So, the purely actual actualizer is fully good. (2017, p. 35)

Feser’s definition of omnipotence is also a very weak one: to be omnipotent is simply to be that from which all creatures’ power derives. From Feser’s definition, it would follow that the Creator of a universe containing only one hydrogen atom would be ipso facto omnipotent!

Omnipotence

33. To have power means to actualize potentials.

34. Any potential that is actualized is either actualized by the purely actual actualizer or by a series of actualizers which terminates in the purely actualizer.

35. So, all power derives from the purely actual actualizer.

36. But to be that from which all power derives is to be omnipotent.

37. So, the purely actual actualizer is omnipotent. (2017, p. 36)

Feser’s argument for God’s omniscience relies on the poorly argued assumption that there is one purely actual actualizer which is the cause of all things. In my previous post, I critiqued the logic of Feser’s argument for Divine omniscience on two additional grounds – namely, the flawed assumption that having an intellect which contains all forms (or concepts) entails having knowledge (which overlooks the fact that the knowledge of a state of affairs is essentially propositional), plus the misguided attempt to infer God’s knowledge of all propositions from God’s causation of all states of affairs (an inference which overlooks the fact that it is beings and their properties that require an explanation, according to the Thomistic version of the Principle of Sufficient Reason – not states of affairs). Feser of course denies that God’s knowledge is propositional – a claim which I criticized in a previous post.

Omniscience

38. Whatever is in an effect is in its cause in some way, whether formally, virtually, or eminently (the principle of proportionate causality).

39. The purely actual actualizer is the cause of all things.

40. So, the forms or patterns manifest in all the things it causes must in some way be in the purely actual actualizer.

41. These forms or patterns can exist either in the concrete way in which they exist in individual particular things, or in the abstract way in which they exist in the thoughts of an intellect.

42. They cannot exist in the purely actual actualizer in the same way they exist in individual particular things.

43. So, they must exist in the purely actual actualizer in the abstract way in which they exist in the thoughts of an intellect.

44. So, the purely actual actualizer has intellect or intelligence.

45. Since it is the forms or patterns of all things that are in the thoughts of this intellect, there is nothing that is outside the range of those thoughts.

46. For there to be nothing outside the range of something’s thoughts is for that thing to be omniscient.

47. So, the purely actual actualizer is omniscient. (2017, p. 36)

Feser then wraps up his argument: since there exists a purely actual cause of the existence of things, which is one, immutable, eternal, immaterial, incorporeal, perfect, fully good, omnipotent, intelligent, and omniscient, and since for God to exist is for such a cause of things to exist, we may legitimately conclude that God exists. By now, I hope that readers will have come to realize that the notion of a purely actual Being is an oxymoron, as I have argued in a previous post.

Having rejected Feser’s first and second proofs of God’s existence on account of their flawed logic, bad mereology and (as I have argued, bad theology), the task that now confronts us is to examine Feser’s remaining proofs and inquire as to whether they can be cut free from their Aristotelian moorings and resurrected in a new form, as powerful arguments for the existence of God. That will be the subject of my future posts.

21 thoughts on “Flawed logic and bad mereology: why Feser’s first two proofs fail

  1. VJ,
    There is no doubt in my mind that as usual you have put a lot of effort and time into your OP. However, I ‘d like to know how many people will actually read your OP to the end… I’m not saying it is interesting. It is just long and today, people’s attention span is very, very short… If you don’t catch readers’ attention within 30 seconds and continue to keep them interested every minute or so, they are unlikely to continue to read… IMO…

  2. Hi J-Mac and quarrion,

    That line about the movie was funny. I had a chuckle over that.

    Seriously, though: for those readers who were disinclined to read my post in its entirety, I did provide a summary in my opening few paragraphs, and I also provided a menu for people who might have wanted to read one section at a time, or scroll back and forth. I also wrote a summary of my argument for the longer parts (B and C).

    The reason why my post was a long one is that Feser’s first two proofs are quite complex, and they need to be understood in their entirety before one can properly criticize them. To make matters even more difficult, Feser buttresses his initial arguments with subsequent clarifying remarks made in later chapters of his book, and I had to cover what he wrote in those chapters too, so as not to be accused of doing him an injustice, or misrepresenting him.

    I will, however, promise you one thing: my next few posts will be much shorter than this one.

  3. Hi, Vince.

    My own difficulty in getting through this OP, which covers a bunch of issues I find interesting in impressive depth is not actually its length. There’s a ton of good stuff here, but you bounce around too much, IMHO. When I think you are going to concentrate on an argument and show what is right or wrong about it, you will instead go off on some other issue for awhile. Maybe come back to where you were, maybe not.

    You’re a smart and industrious man, and I have no doubt that you’ve got a really good book on Feser (or arguments for God, generally) in you, but I think you’ll need an editor. Maybe even a co-author. I hope you don’t mind me being frank in this way.

    One other thing that struck me.

    Readers may be wondering why I, as a religious believer, am attacking Feser’s first two proofs with such gusto. My reasons can be summed up in four words: Divine and human freedom. If you accept Feser’s argument that there exists a purely actual, absolutely simple Being, then two things follow: first, you have no more freedom than a character in a novel does, which means that your Maker cannot hold you morally accountable for your misdeeds, even if other people do; and second, the Being Who created you lacks the capacity to make free choices (scroll down to section 4, on God’s Will), as it has no potentialities which it is capable of realizing.

    This psychological disclosure may be interesting on a personal level, but it suggests bias to me. If Feser’s arguments are good and entail that you have no free will, then you have no free will. Your unhappiness with any such conclusion is neither here nor there.

  4. I wonder if the problem here lies with Feser or if it runs deeper into Thomism. Maybe the problem arises from Feser being too Aristotelian in his Thomism.

    The Aristotelian “unmoved mover” is a purely actual being — a being that has no potency or potential. As such it cannot contemplate alternatives or make choices. It has no “free will”, and it less a Creator and more of a Eternal Organizer. Since Aristotle does not believe that the universe had a beginning, the role of the Unmoved Mover is not to cause the universe to begin. Rather the Unmoved Mover is the cause of all things as their final cause: the unmoved mover draws all things to itself.

    The movement from potency to actuality in all things is a result of how all things are drawn to the purest actuality of all. And the unmoved mover does this without any will, intent, or any other psychological state or propositional attitude. It is pure thought, and it takes only itself as the object of its thought — thought thinking itself is the highest or purest form of actuality.

    Given these Aristotelian commitments to what pure actuality would have to be like, it’s really hard to square that with a God who loves humanity, who created all things (even Hell, as Dante reminds us) out of eternal love, and who sacrificed Himself in the person of the Son so that everyone would be reconciled to Him. This entire drama of sin and salvation, the beating heart of Christian faith, is at odds with the Aristotelian unmoved mover, who cares for us no more than the gods of Epicurus can. (Bear in mind that Epicurus’s argument that the gods are too perfect to take notice of us was a premise in his argument for practical atheism: since they do not notice us, we should pay no attention to them.)

    Obviously, I know that Aquinas and subsequent Thomists have ways of reconciling Aristotle and Scripture. But reading this OP, I’m wondering if Feser has lost his grip on the Thomistic synthesis of Aristotle and Scripture and gone too far towards a strictly Aristotelian position.

  5. walto: This psychological disclosure may be interesting on a personal level, but it suggests bias to me. If Feser’s arguments are good and entail that you have no free will, then you have no free will. Your unhappiness with any such conclusion is neither here nor there.

    I don’t know if I completely agree. Maybe 90% agreement.

    I think there’s something to the idea that one function of metaphysics is to bring systematicity and consistency into the background assumptions that structure our everyday engagement with the world.

    If the metaphysics says that there’s no free will, and the commitment to free will is too deeply interwoven with our everyday practices (e.g. Strawson’s reactive attitude argument?), then maybe “so much the worse for metaphysics!” is the right response?

    Personally, I don’t think we have free will, at least not the kind of free will that Augustine, Aquinas, and Descartes all thought we had — genuinely libertarian freedom that initiates new causal chains ex nihilo. I’m with Dennett in thinking that being able to predict possibilities and plan accordingly is pretty much all the “free will” that we need. But then again, I’m one of those Spinozists that your mother warned you about.

  6. Kantian Naturalist,

    Yes, I think it’s right to point out the entailment and let the chips fall where they may. If free will seems more evident to Vince than some premise that Feser is relying on, that’s worth a mention. And if others share his intuitions, they may come to the same conclusions. But it’s a modus ponens/modus tollens standoff if Feser doesn’t share them.

    Incidentally, do you share my sense of organizational defects with this OP? I found it hard to find a foothold where I could begin a careful assessment. Jumps around too much, I think.

  7. Hi walto and Kantian Naturalist,

    I appreciate frank criticism, and I welcome your comments. You’re right about my needing an editor, walto: personally, I find it very hard to put together an article (let alone a book) about such complex (and interesting) arguments for the existence of God, in a way that doesn’t “bounce around.” By the way, have you finished reading Feser’s book? I’d be interested to hear your impressions of it.

    Kantian Naturalist, I thought you made a very telling point about the difficulty of squaring the Aristotelian unmoved mover, “who cares for us no more than the gods of Epicurus can,” with “a God who loves humanity, who created all things (even Hell, as Dante reminds us) out of eternal love, and who sacrificed Himself in the person of the Son so that everyone would be reconciled to Him.” Perhaps Dr. Feser’s first proof is too Aristotelian, as you suggest.

    Re free will: you both seem to think it would have been better for me to simply the metaphysical implications of Feser’s argument and “let the chips fall where they may.” Maybe you’re right. However, I’m not simply arguing that Feser’s arguments must be wrong because they imply that we don’t have libertarian free will: I also wanted to show that his case for a purely actual and absolutely simple Being is an unconvincing one. But even if it were airtight, it would still make no sense for Feser to maintain, as a Catholic, that this purely actual Being can hold us morally accountable for our misdeeds. As I argued in an earlier post, an author doesn’t blame the characters in his book for the things that they do, even if some of the characters in the book end up blaming each other.

    Anyway, thank you both for your thoughtful feedback.

  8. I haven’t read any of Feser’s book, except what you have excerpted for us (for which, many thanks). Looks pretty meaty, but not really in my wheelhouse (since grad school anyhow). If you do finish a book draft, I will look at it for you if you like–and I’m not otherwise engaged. It’s a pretty big commitment!

  9. vjtorley: Re free will: you both seem to think it would have been better for me to simply the metaphysical implications of Feser’s argument and “let the chips fall where they may.” Maybe you’re right. However, I’m not simply arguing that Feser’s arguments must be wrong because they imply that we don’t have libertarian free will: I also wanted to show that his case for a purely actual and absolutely simple Being is an unconvincing one. But even if it were airtight, it would still make no sense for Feser to maintain, as a Catholic, that this purely actual Being can hold us morally accountable for our misdeeds. As I argued in an earlier post, an author doesn’t blame the characters in his book for the things that they do, even if some of the characters in the book end up blaming each other.

    I think that this is a nice point at which to push even more on the relation between Feser’s Aristotelianism and his Catholicism. With regard to an internal criticism of Feser, the question would be, could a purely actual being hold us morally accountable? This is a question not just about whether we have free will but also about whether God has, if not free will, something similar & perhaps that of which our free will is the imago Dei.

    One problem here is that a purely actual being cannot choose to create. Another problem is that, if we are somehow “made in the image” of a purely actual being, and our deficiencies are due to not being purely actual, then we’re losing our grip on the distinction between akrasia and sin — between merely lacking the ability to resist wrongdoing (say, due to inadequate moral education or some deficit in self-control) and actively choosing it. And if there’s no difference there, then there’s no conceptual basis for Christianity.

  10. Hi Kantian Naturalist,

    You pose a very interesting question: what would it mean to be made in the image of a purely actual Being? Indeed, if God is construed in that way, it’s hard to see how any creature could even come close to being called an image of its Creator. What that suggests to me is that God’s actuality cannot be what’s most fundamental about Him. We need a deeper concept of God.

  11. Is it possible to have a deeper concept of god before establishing that such a being exists? Should we place much weight on the idea that we are images of our creator without first establishing that we do indeed have a creator and that there is some evidence that we were created in its image?

  12. vjtorley:
    Hi Kantian Naturalist,

    You pose a very interesting question: what would it mean to be made in the image of a purely actual Being? Indeed, if God is construed in that way, it’s hard to see how any creature could even come close to being called an image of its Creator. What that suggests to me is that God’s actuality cannot be what’s most fundamental about Him. We need a deeper concept of God.

    Being made in the image of God can’t be understood literally…
    If that were the case, we’d be one person made of three separate beings one of which could at least be represented as a dove, fire and wind…
    Unless of course God meant to give us all a multiple personality disorder…

  13. J-Mac: Being made in the image of God can’t be understood literally

    Yes, I understand it’s meant to refer to any manufacturer of dairy products.

  14. John Harshman: Yes, I understand it’s meant to refer to any manufacturer of dairy products.

    Yes! Yes! Yes! Just like the manufacturer of the natural processes, namely sheer dumb luck… See the connection?

  15. J-Mac: Yes! Yes! Yes! Just like the manufacturer of the natural processes, namely sheer dumb luck… See the connection?

    No.

  16. J-Mac: So now you know how I feel about your previous comment…

    You could have asked. Have you seen Life of Brian?

  17. vjtorley, to KN:

    You pose a very interesting question: what would it mean to be made in the image of a purely actual Being? Indeed, if God is construed in that way, it’s hard to see how any creature could even come close to being called an image of its Creator. What that suggests to me is that God’s actuality cannot be what’s most fundamental about Him. We need a deeper concept of God.

    Vincent,

    You’re giving a lot of weight to the idea that we’re created in God’s image, but why?

  18. Hi, vjtorley

    Your subsection entitled “Feser’s nine-step argument for a purely actual actualizer”, under Chapter 2. “The logic of Feser’s argument for the existence of a First Actualizer”, severely misrepresents Feser’s argument. Premises 6A-7 of your representation conclude at premise 8 that any substance S has at any moment some actualizer A of its existence. But the statement in your premise 8 is exactly what Feser’s argument attempts to prove false! Feser argues that there IS a thing or substance that does not at any moment have an actualizer A of its existence; that there is a Purely Actual Actualizer.

    Premise 8 in your argument is not identical to premise 8 of Feser’s argument. The sentences are the same, but the statements are not. In your representation of Feser’s argument, the variable “S” in premise 8 references some thing or substance, because that’s what the variable referenced when it was introduced in premise 6A. But in Feser’s actual argument, the variable “S” in premise 8 specifically and crucially references some thing or substance which changes, because that’s what the variable referenced when it was introduced in his premise 6. Of course, you missed the difference between your premise 8 and Feser’s premise 8 because you tossed away the premise in which Feser mentioned what the variable “S” stood for in his argument.

    Indeed, you misrepresent it in such a way as to prompt the “if everything has a cause, then what caused God” objection. After all, if your premise 8 is right that everything or every substance has at any moment an actualizer A of its existence, and if the purely actual actualizer is a thing or substance (which it is, according to your definition of “substance”), then the purely actual actualizer requires a cause. Your representation of Feser’s argument is really the classic “everything has a cause” straw-man that, in all irony, you have worked hard to combat in some of your other posts. Frankly, vjtorely, critics need to stop with all this “paraphrasing” and “nutshelling” of philosophical arguments for God’s existence and just lay out the darn argument the way the theistic philosopher gave it.

    I recommend leaving premises 1-6 of Feser’s argument as they are. The first five premises are not redundant; they argue that potentiality and actuality are real features of the world, which is obviously crucial to the Aristotelian argument. Feser would readily agree that his argument for a purely actual actualizer need not “invoke the occurrence of change in the world”, as you claimed; he has five arguments that each entail, without mentioning change, that there is a purely actual actualizer! Obviously, Feser recognizes that an argument from change in the world is not necessary to support his conclusion. It would just constitute a different argument than the Aristotelian one, that’s all. The Aristotelian argument goes to show that a person may argue from change if that is the particular course of argumentation that he so desires to pursue. I don’t see why your point is to be taken seriously, especially when your dismissal of the so-called redundant premises made room for a disastrous substitute argument, anyways.

Leave a Reply